I don’t think I understand what you’ve written here. It’s indeed possible that the card is not Club when it’s Spade. As a matter of fact, it’s the only possibility, because the card can’t be both Spade and a Club.
There are four different days when SB could be awakened. On three of them, she would not have been awakened if the card was a club. This makes it more likely that the card is a club. This really is very simple probability. If you have difficulty with it, wake her every day. But in the situations where she was left asleep before, wake her and ask her for the probability that the card is the Ace of Clubs.
My points are that (A) the event where SB is left asleep is still an event in SB’s sample space, (B) her “new information” is that she is observing the event in her sample space that match certain conditions, not that the negation of that event is not a part of her sample space, and (C) the amnesia drug disassociates the current day from all others.
This … doesn’t affect the probability to be awaken in the experiment.
Yes, it does. We can argue back and forth about who is correct, but all you have provided is word salad to support a conclusion you reached before choosing the logic. I keep providing examples that contradict it, and your counter-argument is that it contradicts your word salad.
Try another example; and this is actually closer to Zuboff’s original problem than Elga’s version of it, or the version he solved which has become the canonical form. (It’s problem is that the Monday:Tuesday difference obfuscates the probability.)
2N players agree to the following game, and are fully informed of all details. Before the game starts, each is put to sleep. Over the next N days, each will be wakened on either every one of the N days, or on a single, randomly-selected day in the interval, based on the result of a single coin flip that applies to all 2N players and all days. With 2 possible flip results, and N days, each player is randomly assigned a different combination of a coin result and a day.
On each day, each of the N+1 players who are wakened is asked for her probability/credence/confidence/whatever for the proposition that she will be wakened only once. After answering, each will be put back to sleep with amnesia.
In Zuboff’s version, N=one trillion, and the day is random, the coin result is unspecified, but this is the question the player is asked; in other words, it does not matter that the coin result is unspecified.In the problem Elga posed, N=2 but the days are not specified, and the question is effectively the same since Heads is specified. In the problem Elga solved, N=2, the day is day #1, and Heads is specified.
Nothing about these variations change the solution methodology.
The halfer solution is that each of the N+1 players who are awake should say the probability that this is her only waking is 1⁄2. And that each of the other N awake payers should answer the same. This is despite the fact that she knows, for a fact, that only one of the N+1 awake players satisfies the proposition. Additionally, they can assign a probability of 1⁄2 to an asleep player, despite knowing that this player does satisfy the proposition.
These are not probabilities but weighted probabilities, where the measure function is re-normalized by the number of awakenings, even though the awakenings are not mutually exclusive.
These are not weighted probabilities, they are probabilities using all of the 4*52=208, equally-likely members of the prior sample space that can apply to a randomly-selected day in the experiment. They are mutually exclusive, to SB, because the amnesia drug isolates each day from the others that may be “sequential” with it, whatever that is supposed to mean to SB since she sees only one day.
Sigh. We’ve been through it a couple of times already.
Yes, we have, and you ignore every point I make.
The prior sample space depends on which observations is possible to make in the experiment at all, according to the prior knowledge state of a particular person.
A prior sample space depends ONLY on how the circumstances occur. Observation has nothing to do with it.
On HEADS+TUESDAY, wake SB but take her on a shopping spree instead of interviewing her. When interviewed, should she think that Pr(H)=1/2, or Pr(H)=1/3? Of course it is 1⁄3, because her set of possible observations includes four (not two) mutually exclusive outcomes, with one ruled out by observation. My point is that she knows she is in NOT(H&Tue) regardless of what observation is possible in H&Tue.
{H&Mon, T&Mon, H&Tue T&Tue} is a sample space for observer problem, not for SB. For a researcher working on a random day, observing outcome T&Tue is a priori possible, for the Beauty participating on every day, it’s not.
{H&Mon, T&Mon, H&Tue T&Tue} is the set of possible circumstances for a single day in the experiment. The “observer problem” you describe includes only two outcomes, Heads and Tails. Both Monday and Tuesday exist in each observation, since they are not isolated by amnesia. What you listed is the sample space when the random experiment can include only one day—AMNESIA!! H&Tue is in SB’s prior = unaffected by observation sample space.
My generalized version of Zuboff’s problem has 2N members in its sample space. When a player is awake, N+1 of these members are consistent with observation. One matches the proposition that the player will be wakened once. Making the probability of the proposition 1/(N+1).
In the canonical SB problem, N=2 and the probability is 1/(N+1)=1/3.
Contrary to what too many want to believe, probability theory does not define what “the probability” is. It only defines these (simplified) rules that the values must adhere to:
Every probability is greater than, or equal to, zero.
The probability of the union of two distinct outcomes A and B is Pr(A)+Pr(B).
The probability of the universal event (all possible outcomes) is 1.
Let A=”googolth digit of pi is odd”, and B=”googolth digit of pi is even.” These required properties only guarantee that Pr(A)+Pr(B)=1, and that each is a non-zero number. We only “intuitively” say that Pr(A)=Pr(B)=0.5 because we have no reason to state otherwise. That is, we can’t assert that Pr(A)>Pr(B) or Pr(A)<Pr(B), so we can only assume that Pr(A)=Pr(B). But given a reason, we can change this.
The point is that there are no “right” or “wrong” statements in probability. Only statements where the probabilities adhere to these requirements. We can never say what a “probability is,” but we can rule out some sets of probabilities that violate these rules.