Programme Director at UK Advanced Research + Invention Agency focusing on safe transformative AI; formerly Protocol Labs, FHI/Oxford, Harvard Biophysics, MIT Mathematics And Computation.
davidad
Nice, thanks for the pointer!
Paralysis of the form “AI system does nothing” is the most likely failure mode. This is a “de-pessimizing” agenda at the meta-level as well as at the object-level. Note, however, that there are some very valuable and ambitious tasks (e.g. build robots that install solar panels without damaging animals or irreversibly affecting existing structures, and only talking to people via a highly structured script) that can likely be specified without causing paralysis, even if they fall short of ending the acute risk period.
“Locked into some least-harmful path” is a potential failure mode if the semantics or implementation of causality or decision theory in the specification framework are done in a different way than I hope. Locking in to a particular path massively reduces the entropy of the outcome distribution beyond what is necessary to ensure a reasonable risk threshold (e.g. 1 catastrophic event per millennium) is cleared. A FEEF objective (namely, minimize the divergence of the outcomes conditional on intervention from the outcomes conditional on filtering for the goal being met) would greatly penalize the additional facts which are enforced by the lock-in behaviours.
As a fail-safe, I propose to mitigate the downsides of lock-in by using time-bounded utility functions.
It seems plausible to me that, until ambitious value alignment is solved, ASL-4+ systems ought not to have any mental influences on people other than those which factor through the system’s pre-agreed goals being achieved in the world. That is, ambitious value alignment seems like a necessary prerequisite for the safety of ASL-4+ general-purpose chatbots. However, world-changing GDP growth does not require such general-purpose capabilities to be directly available (rather than available via a sociotechnical system that involves agreeing on specifications and safety guardrails for particular narrow deployments).
It is worth noting here that a potential failure mode is that a truly malicious general-purpose system in the box could decide to encode harmful messages in irrelevant details of the engineering designs (which it then proves satisfy the safety specifications). But, I think sufficient fine-tuning with a GFlowNet objective will naturally penalise description complexity, and also penalise heavily biased sampling of equally complex solutions (e.g. toward ones that encode messages of any significance), and I expect this to reduce this risk to an acceptable level. I would like to fund a sleeper-agents-style experiment on this by the end of 2025.
Re footnote 2, and the claim that the order matters, do you have a concrete example of a homogeneous ultradistribution that is affine in one sense but not the other?
The “random dictator” baseline should not be interpreted as allowing the random dictator to dictate everything, but rather to dictate which Pareto improvement is chosen (with the baseline for “Pareto improvement” being “no superintelligence”). Hurting heretics is not a Pareto improvement because it makes those heretics worse off than if there were no superintelligence.
What does davidad want from «boundaries»?
Yes. You will find more details in his paper, Provably safe systems with Steve Omohundro, in which I am listed in the acknowledgments (under my legal name, David Dalrymple).
Max and I also met and discussed the similarities in advance of the AI Safety Summit in Bletchley.
I agree that each of and has two algebraically equivalent interpretations, as you say, where one is about inconsistency and the other is about inferiority for the adversary. (I hadn’t noticed that).
The variant still seems somewhat irregular to me; even though Diffractor does use it in Infra-Miscellanea Section 2, I wouldn’t select it as “the” infrabayesian monad. I’m also confused about which one you’re calling unbounded. It seems to me like the variant is bounded (on both sides) whereas the variant is bounded on one side, and neither is really unbounded. (Being bounded on at least one side is of course necessary for being consistent with infinite ethics.)
These are very good questions. First, two general clarifications:
A. «Boundaries» are not partitions of physical space; they are partitions of a causal graphical model that is an abstraction over the concrete physical world-model.
B. To “pierce” a «boundary» is to counterfactually (with respect to the concrete physical world-model) cause the abstract model that represents the boundary to increase in prediction error (relative to the best augmented abstraction that uses the same state-space factorization but permits arbitrary causal dependencies crossing the boundary).
So, to your particular cases:
Probably not. There is no fundamental difference between sound and contact. Rather, the fundamental difference is between the usual flow of information through the senses and other flows of information that are possible in the concrete physical world-model but not represented in the abstraction. An interaction that pierces the membrane is one which breaks the abstraction barrier of perception. Ordinary speech acts do not. Only sounds which cause damage (internal state changes that are not well-modelled as mental states) or which otherwise exceed the “operating conditions” in the state space of the «boundary» layer (e.g. certain kinds of superstimuli) would pierce the «boundary».
Almost surely not. This is why, as an agenda for AI safety, it will be necessary to specify a handful of constructive goals, such as provision of clean water and sustenance and the maintenance of hospitable atmospheric conditions, in addition to the «boundary»-based safety prohibitions.
Definitely not. Omission of beneficial actions is not a counterfactual impact.
Probably. This causes prediction error because the abstraction of typical human spatial positions is that they have substantial ability to affect their position between nearby streets by simple locomotory action sequences. But if a human is already effectively imprisoned, then adding more concrete would not create additional/counterfactual prediction error.
Probably not. Provision of resources (that are within “operating conditions”, i.e. not “out-of-distribution”) is not a «boundary» violation as long as the human has the typical amount of control of whether to accept them.
Definitely not. Exploiting behavioural tendencies which are not counterfactually corrupted is not a «boundary» violation.
Maybe. If the ad’s effect on decision-making tendencies is well modelled by the abstraction of typical in-distribution human interactions, then using that channel does not violate the «boundary». Unprecedented superstimuli would, but the precedented patterns in advertising are already pretty bad. This is a weak point of the «boundaries» concept, in my view. We need additional criteria for avoiding psychological harm, including superpersuasion. One is simply to forbid autonomous superhuman systems from communicating to humans at all: any proposed actions which can be meaningfully interpreted by sandboxed human-level supervisory AIs as messages with nontrivial semantics could be rejected. Another approach is Mariven’s criterion for deception, but applying this criterion requires modelling human mental states as beliefs about the world (which is certainly not 100% scientifically accurate). I would like to see more work here, and more different proposed approaches.
- 5 Jan 2024 1:45 UTC; 1 point) 's comment on Agent membranes/boundaries and formalizing “safety” by (
For the record, as this post mostly consists of quotes from me, I can hardly fail to endorse it.
Kosoy’s infrabayesian monad is given by
There are a few different varieties of infrabayesian belief-state, but I currently favour the one which is called “homogeneous ultracontributions”, which is “non-empty topologically-closed ⊥–closed convex sets of subdistributions”, thus almost exactly the same as Mio-Sarkis-Vignudelli’s “non-empty finitely-generated ⊥–closed convex sets of subdistributions monad” (Definition 36 of this paper), with the difference being essentially that it’s presentable, but it’s much more like than .
I am not at all convinced by the interpretation of here as terminating a game with a reward for the adversary or the agent. My interpretation of the distinguished element in is not that it represents a special state in which the game is over, but rather a special state in which there is a contradiction between some of one’s assumptions/observations. This is very useful for modelling Bayesian updates (Evidential Decision Theory via Partial Markov Categories, sections 3.5-3.6), in which some variable is observed to satisfy a certain predicate : this can be modelled by applying the predicate in the form where means the predicate is false, and means it is true. But I don’t think there is a dual to logical inconsistency, other than the full set of all possible subdistributions on the state space. It is certainly not the same type of “failure” as losing a game.
Does this article have any practical significance, or is it all just abstract nonsense? How does this help us solve the Big Problem? To be perfectly frank, I have no idea. Timelines are probably too short agent foundations, and this article is maybe agent foundations foundations...
I do think this is highly practically relevant, not least of which because using an infrabayesian monad instead of the distribution monad can provide the necessary kind of epistemic conservatism for practical safety verification in complex cyber-physical systems like the biosphere being protected and the cybersphere being monitored. It also helps remove instrumentally convergent perverse incentives to control everything.
Meyer’s
If this is David Jaz Myers, it should be “Myers’ thesis”, here and elsewhere
I have said many times that uploads created by any process I know of so far would probably be unable to learn or form memories. (I think it didn’t come up in this particular dialogue, but in the unanswered questions section Jacob mentions having heard me say it in the past.)
Eliezer has also said that makes it useless in terms of decreasing x-risk. I don’t have a strong inside view on this question one way or the other. I do think if Factored Cognition is true then “that subset of thinking is enough,” but I have a lot of uncertainty about whether Factored Cognition is true.
Anyway, even if that subset of thinking is enough, and even if we could simulate all the true mechanisms of plasticity, then I still don’t think this saves the world, personally, which is part of why I am not in fact pursuing uploading these days.
Does davidad’s uploading moonshot work?
I think AI Safety Levels are a good idea, but evals-based classification needs to be complemented by compute thresholds to mitigate the risks of loss of control via deceptive alignment. Here is a non-nebulous proposal.
I like the idea of trying out H-JEPA with GFlowNet actors.
I also like the idea of using LLM-based virtue ethics as a regularizer, although I would still want deontic guardrails that seem good enough to avoid catastrophe.
Yes, it’s the latter. See also the Open Agency Keyholder Prize.
That’s basically correct. OAA is more like a research agenda and a story about how one would put the research outputs together to build safe AI, than an engineering agenda that humanity entirely knows how to build. Even I think it’s only about 30% likely to work in time.
I would love it if humanity had a plan that was more likely to be feasible, and in my opinion that’s still an open problem!
Yes, I am indeed thinking about this.
Let’s first consider the easiest case, in which we ask for a solution/output to be not merely provably correct according to some spec, but provably unique. Then there is clearly no space for steganography.
It is a little bit harder if the solution has some symmetries, like permutations of the order in which things are serialized. For this we can use sorting and other normalization techniques (converting an output to a unique representative of its equivalence class).
If normalization is hard, we can set up the box to be interactive, so that users cannot see the solution, but can only run queries on it (e.g. “next action please”) and the user must prove that the queries are invariant under (aka “respect”) the equivalence relation.
But for most real-world problems there are many equally specification-satisfying strategies that are not behaviourally equivalent. The next hardest thing to do is to establish an upper bound on the log-cardinality of the set of behavioural-equivalence-classes that satisfy the specification. We want to keep the channel capacity (in bits per day) available for steganography, to humans or insecure cyber-infrastructure or biosequence synthesis, to a very low threshold (maybe 2 bits per day is okay).
Often there will be too many degrees of freedom for this, so instead we need to do entropy regularization, which can be done elegantly with GFlowNets. I have not worked out all the details here but the hope is that we can derive a sound bound or PAC estimate of the KL divergence of the observable behaviour (which is sampled from the policy distribution dependent upon a stream of certified randomness) from the Frechet mean/centroid of all correct behaviours. This quantity would provide an upper bound on how much information the optimization process inside the box can transmit to the outside by having selecting a biased policy distribution.