There’s a sense in which a lot of fuzzy claims are meaningless: for example, it would be hard for a computer to evaluate “Socrates is kind” even if the computer could easily evaluate more direct claims like “Socrates is taller than five feet”. But “kind” isn’t really meaningless; it would just be a lot of work to establish exactly what goes into saying “kind” and exactly where the cutoff point between “kind” and “not so kind” is.
I agree that literary critical terms are fuzzy in the same sense as “kind”, but I don’t think they’re necessarily any more fuzzy. For example, replacing “post-utopian” with its likely inspiration “post-colonial”, I don’t know much about literature, but I feel pretty okay designating Salman Rushdie as “post-colonial” (since his books very often take place against the backdrop of the issues surrounding British decolonization of India) and J. K. Rowling as “not post-colonial” (since her books don’t deal with issues surrounding decolonization at all.)
Likewise, even though “post-utopian” was chosen specifically to be meaningless, I can say with confidence that Sir Thomas More’s Utopia was not post-utopian, and I bet most other people will agree with me.
The Sokal Hoax to me was less about totally disproving all literary critical terms, and more about showing that it’s really easy to get a paper published that no one understands. People elsewhere in the thread have already given examples of Sokalesque papers in physics, computer science, etc that got published, even though those fields seem pretty meaningful.
Literary criticism does have a bad habit of making strange assertions, but I don’t think they hinge on meaningless terms. A good example would be deconstruction of various works to point out the racist or sexist elements within. For example, “It sure is suspicious that Moby Dick is about a white whale, as if Melville believed that only white animals could possibly be individuals with stories of their own.”
The claim that Melville was racist when writing Moby Dick seems potentially meaningful—for example, we could go back in time, put him under truth serum, and ask him whether that was intentional. Even if it was wholly unconscious, it still implies that (for example) if we simulate a society without racism, it will be less likely to produce books like Moby Dick, or that if we pick apart Melville’s brain we can draw some causal connection between the racism to which he was exposed and the choice to have Moby Dick be white.
However, if I understand correctly literary critics believe these assertions do not hinge on authorial intent; that is, Melville might not have been trying to make Moby Dick a commentary on race relations, but that doesn’t mean a paper claiming that Moby Dick is a commentary on race relations should be taken less seriously.
Even this might not be totally meaningless. If an infinite monkey at an infinite typewriter happened to produce Animal Farm, it would still be the case that, by coincidence, it was a great metaphor for Communism. A literary critic (or primatologist) who wrote a paper saying “Hey, Animal Farm can increase our understanding and appreciation of the perils of Communism” wouldn’t really be talking nonsense. In fact, I’d go so far as to say that they’re (kind of) objectively correct, whereas even someone making the relatively stupid claim about Moby Dick above might still be right that the book can help us think about our assumptions about white people.
If I had to criticize literary criticism, I would have a few vague objections. First, that they inflate terms—instead of saying “Moby Dick vaguely reminds me of racism”, they say “Moby Dick is about racism.” Second, that even if their terms are not meaningless, their disputes very often are: if one critic says “Moby Dick is about racism” and another critic says “No it isn’t”, then if what the first one means is “Mobdy Dick vaguely reminds me of racism”, then arguing this is a waste of time. My third and most obvious complaint is opportunity costs: to me at least the whole field of talking about how certain things vaguely remind you of other things seems like a waste of resources that could be turned into perfectly good paper clips.
But these seem like very different criticisms than arguing that their terms are literally meaningless. I agree that to students they may be meaningless and they might compensate by guessing the teacher’s password, but this happens in every field.
I liked your comment and have a half-formed metaphor for you to either pick apart or develop:
LW/ rationalist types tend towards hard sciences. This requires more System 2 reasoning. Their fields are like computer programs. Every step makes sense, and is understood.
Humanities tends toward more System 1 pattern recognition. This is more akin to a neural network. Even if you are getting the “right” answer, it is coming out of a black box.
Because the rationalist types can’t see the algorithm, they assume it can’t be “right”.
I like the idea that this comment produces in my mind. But nitpickingly, a neural network is a type of computer program. And most of the professional bollocks-talkers of my acquaintance think very hard in system-two like ways about the rubbish they spout.
It’s hard to imagine a system-one academic discipline. Something like ‘Professor of telling whether people you are looking at are angry’, or ‘Professor of catching cricket balls’....
I wonder if you might be thinking more of the difference between a computer program that one fully understands (a rare thing indeed), and one which is only dimly understood, and made up of ‘magical’ parts even though its top level behaviour may be reasonably predictable (which is how most programmers perceive most programs).
Well, in the case of answers to questions like that in the humanities what does the word ‘right’ actually mean? If we say a particular author is ‘post utopian’ what does it actually mean for the answer to that question to be ‘yes’ or ‘no’? It’s just a classification that we invented. And like all classification groups there is a set of rules characteristics that mean that the author is either post utopian or not. I imagine it as a checklist of features which gets ticked off as a person reads the book. If all the items in the checklist are ticked then the author is post utopian. If not then the author is not.
The problem with this is that different people have different items in their checklist and differ in their opinion on how many items in the list need to be checked for the author to be classified as post utopian. You can pick any literary classification and this will be the case. There will never be a consensus on all the items in the checklist. There will always be a few points that everybody does not agree on. This makes me think that objectively speaking there is not ‘absolutely right’ or ‘absolutely wrong’ answer to a question like that.
In hard science on the other hand. There is always an absolutely right answer. If we say: “Protons and neutrons are oppositely charged.” There is an answer that is right because no matter what my beliefs, experiment is the final arbiter. Nobody who follows through the logical steps can deny that they are oppositely charged without making an illogical leap.
In the literary classification, you or your neural network can go through logical steps and still arrive at an answer that is not the same for everybody.
EDIT: I meant “protons and electrons are oppositely charged” not “protons and neutrons”. Sorry!
One: Protons and neutrons aren’t oppositely charged.
Two: You’re using particle physics as an example of an area where experiment is the final arbiter; you might not want to do that. Scientific consensus has more than a few established beliefs in that field that are untested and border on untestable.
Honestly, he’d be hard pressed to find a field that has better tested beliefs and greater convergence of evidence. The established beliefs you mention are a problem everywhere, and pretty much no field is backed with as much data as particle physics.
Fair enough; I had wanted to say that but don’t have sufficiently intimate awareness of every academic field to be comfortable doing so. I think it works just as well to illustrate that we oughtn’t confuse passing flaws in a field with fundamental ones, or the qualities of a /discipline/ with the qualities of seeking truth in a particular domain.
No, it’s just that FluffyC used slashes to indicate that the word in the middle was to be italisized, so she probably hadn’t read the help section, and I thought that reading the help section would, well, help FluffyC.
I don’t think that the fact that everyone having a different checklist is the point. In this perfect, hypothetical world, everyone has the same checklist.
I think that the point is that the checklist is meaningless, like having a literary genre called y-ism and having “The letter ‘y’ constitutes 1/26th of the text” on the checklist.
Even if we can identify y-ism with our senses, the distinction is doesn’t “mean” anything. It has zero application outside of the world of y-ism. It floats.
I agree that literary critical terms are fuzzy in the same sense as “kind”, but I don’t think they’re necessarily any more fuzzy.
That is an important point. It is not so easy to come up up with a criterion of “meaningfulness” that excludes the stuff rationalists don’t like, but doens’t exclude a lot of everyday terninology at the same time.
I could add that others have their own criteria of “meaningfulness”. Humanities types aren’t very bothered about questions like how many moons saturn has, because it doens’t affect them or their society. The common factor seems to both kinds of “meaningfullness” is that they amount to “the stuff I personally consider to be worth bothering about”.
A concern with objective meaningfullness is still a subjective concern.
FWIW, the Moby Dick example is less stupid than you paint it, given the recurrence of whiteness as an attribute of things special or good in western culture—an idea that pre-dates the invention of race. I think a case could be made out that (1) the causality runs from whiteness as a special or magical attribute, to its selection as a pertinent physical feature when racism was being invented (considering that there were a number of parallel candidates, like phrenology, that didn’t do so well memetically), and (2) in a world that now has racism, the ongoing presence of valuing white things as special has been both consciously used to reinforce it (cf the KKK’s name and its connotations) and unconsciously reinforces it by association,
FWIW, the Moby Dick example is less stupid than you paint it, given the recurrence of whiteness as an attribute of things special or good in western culture—an idea that pre-dates the invention of race.
I can’t resist. I think you should read Moby Dick. Whiteness in that novel is not used as any kind of symbol for good:
This elusive quality it is, which causes the thought of whiteness, when divorced from more kindly associations, and coupled with any object terrible in itself, to heighten that terror to the furthest bounds. Witness the white bear of the poles, and the white shark of the tropics; what but their smooth, flaky whiteness makes them the transcendent horrors they are? That ghastly whiteness it is which imparts such an abhorrent mildness, even more loathsome than terrific, to the dumb gloating of their aspect. So that not the fierce-fanged tiger in his heraldic coat can so stagger courage as the white-shrouded bear or shark.
If you want to talk about racism and Moby Dick, talk about Queequeg!
Not that white animals aren’t often associated with good things, but this is not unique in western culture:
So in spring, when appears the constellation Visakha, the Bodhisatwa, under the appearance of a young white elephant of six defenses, with a head the color of cochineal, with tusks shining like gold, perfect in his organs and limbs, entered the right side of his mother, and she, by means of a dream, was conscious of the fact.
There’s a sense in which a lot of fuzzy claims are meaningless: for example, it would be hard for a computer to evaluate “Socrates is kind” even if the computer could easily evaluate more direct claims like “Socrates is taller than five feet”. But “kind” isn’t really meaningless; it would just be a lot of work to establish exactly what goes into saying “kind” and exactly where the cutoff point between “kind” and “not so kind” is.
I agree that literary critical terms are fuzzy in the same sense as “kind”, but I don’t think they’re necessarily any more fuzzy. For example, replacing “post-utopian” with its likely inspiration “post-colonial”, I don’t know much about literature, but I feel pretty okay designating Salman Rushdie as “post-colonial” (since his books very often take place against the backdrop of the issues surrounding British decolonization of India) and J. K. Rowling as “not post-colonial” (since her books don’t deal with issues surrounding decolonization at all.)
Likewise, even though “post-utopian” was chosen specifically to be meaningless, I can say with confidence that Sir Thomas More’s Utopia was not post-utopian, and I bet most other people will agree with me.
The Sokal Hoax to me was less about totally disproving all literary critical terms, and more about showing that it’s really easy to get a paper published that no one understands. People elsewhere in the thread have already given examples of Sokalesque papers in physics, computer science, etc that got published, even though those fields seem pretty meaningful.
Literary criticism does have a bad habit of making strange assertions, but I don’t think they hinge on meaningless terms. A good example would be deconstruction of various works to point out the racist or sexist elements within. For example, “It sure is suspicious that Moby Dick is about a white whale, as if Melville believed that only white animals could possibly be individuals with stories of their own.”
The claim that Melville was racist when writing Moby Dick seems potentially meaningful—for example, we could go back in time, put him under truth serum, and ask him whether that was intentional. Even if it was wholly unconscious, it still implies that (for example) if we simulate a society without racism, it will be less likely to produce books like Moby Dick, or that if we pick apart Melville’s brain we can draw some causal connection between the racism to which he was exposed and the choice to have Moby Dick be white.
However, if I understand correctly literary critics believe these assertions do not hinge on authorial intent; that is, Melville might not have been trying to make Moby Dick a commentary on race relations, but that doesn’t mean a paper claiming that Moby Dick is a commentary on race relations should be taken less seriously.
Even this might not be totally meaningless. If an infinite monkey at an infinite typewriter happened to produce Animal Farm, it would still be the case that, by coincidence, it was a great metaphor for Communism. A literary critic (or primatologist) who wrote a paper saying “Hey, Animal Farm can increase our understanding and appreciation of the perils of Communism” wouldn’t really be talking nonsense. In fact, I’d go so far as to say that they’re (kind of) objectively correct, whereas even someone making the relatively stupid claim about Moby Dick above might still be right that the book can help us think about our assumptions about white people.
If I had to criticize literary criticism, I would have a few vague objections. First, that they inflate terms—instead of saying “Moby Dick vaguely reminds me of racism”, they say “Moby Dick is about racism.” Second, that even if their terms are not meaningless, their disputes very often are: if one critic says “Moby Dick is about racism” and another critic says “No it isn’t”, then if what the first one means is “Mobdy Dick vaguely reminds me of racism”, then arguing this is a waste of time. My third and most obvious complaint is opportunity costs: to me at least the whole field of talking about how certain things vaguely remind you of other things seems like a waste of resources that could be turned into perfectly good paper clips.
But these seem like very different criticisms than arguing that their terms are literally meaningless. I agree that to students they may be meaningless and they might compensate by guessing the teacher’s password, but this happens in every field.
I liked your comment and have a half-formed metaphor for you to either pick apart or develop:
LW/ rationalist types tend towards hard sciences. This requires more System 2 reasoning. Their fields are like computer programs. Every step makes sense, and is understood.
Humanities tends toward more System 1 pattern recognition. This is more akin to a neural network. Even if you are getting the “right” answer, it is coming out of a black box.
Because the rationalist types can’t see the algorithm, they assume it can’t be “right”.
Thoughts?
I like your idea and upvoted the comment, but I don’t know enough about neural networks to have a meaningful opinion on it.
I like the idea that this comment produces in my mind. But nitpickingly, a neural network is a type of computer program. And most of the professional bollocks-talkers of my acquaintance think very hard in system-two like ways about the rubbish they spout.
It’s hard to imagine a system-one academic discipline. Something like ‘Professor of telling whether people you are looking at are angry’, or ‘Professor of catching cricket balls’....
I wonder if you might be thinking more of the difference between a computer program that one fully understands (a rare thing indeed), and one which is only dimly understood, and made up of ‘magical’ parts even though its top level behaviour may be reasonably predictable (which is how most programmers perceive most programs).
Well, in the case of answers to questions like that in the humanities what does the word ‘right’ actually mean? If we say a particular author is ‘post utopian’ what does it actually mean for the answer to that question to be ‘yes’ or ‘no’? It’s just a classification that we invented. And like all classification groups there is a set of rules characteristics that mean that the author is either post utopian or not. I imagine it as a checklist of features which gets ticked off as a person reads the book. If all the items in the checklist are ticked then the author is post utopian. If not then the author is not.
The problem with this is that different people have different items in their checklist and differ in their opinion on how many items in the list need to be checked for the author to be classified as post utopian. You can pick any literary classification and this will be the case. There will never be a consensus on all the items in the checklist. There will always be a few points that everybody does not agree on. This makes me think that objectively speaking there is not ‘absolutely right’ or ‘absolutely wrong’ answer to a question like that.
In hard science on the other hand. There is always an absolutely right answer. If we say: “Protons and neutrons are oppositely charged.” There is an answer that is right because no matter what my beliefs, experiment is the final arbiter. Nobody who follows through the logical steps can deny that they are oppositely charged without making an illogical leap.
In the literary classification, you or your neural network can go through logical steps and still arrive at an answer that is not the same for everybody.
EDIT: I meant “protons and electrons are oppositely charged” not “protons and neutrons”. Sorry!
One: Protons and neutrons aren’t oppositely charged.
Two: You’re using particle physics as an example of an area where experiment is the final arbiter; you might not want to do that. Scientific consensus has more than a few established beliefs in that field that are untested and border on untestable.
Honestly, he’d be hard pressed to find a field that has better tested beliefs and greater convergence of evidence. The established beliefs you mention are a problem everywhere, and pretty much no field is backed with as much data as particle physics.
Fair enough; I had wanted to say that but don’t have sufficiently intimate awareness of every academic field to be comfortable doing so. I think it works just as well to illustrate that we oughtn’t confuse passing flaws in a field with fundamental ones, or the qualities of a /discipline/ with the qualities of seeking truth in a particular domain.
Press the Show help button to figure out how to italisize and bold and all that.
Was this intended to be a response to a different comment?
No, it’s just that FluffyC used slashes to indicate that the word in the middle was to be italisized, so she probably hadn’t read the help section, and I thought that reading the help section would, well, help FluffyC.
Oh Whoops! I mean protons and electrons! Silly mistake!
I don’t think that the fact that everyone having a different checklist is the point. In this perfect, hypothetical world, everyone has the same checklist.
I think that the point is that the checklist is meaningless, like having a literary genre called y-ism and having “The letter ‘y’ constitutes 1/26th of the text” on the checklist.
Even if we can identify y-ism with our senses, the distinction is doesn’t “mean” anything. It has zero application outside of the world of y-ism. It floats.
That is an important point. It is not so easy to come up up with a criterion of “meaningfulness” that excludes the stuff rationalists don’t like, but doens’t exclude a lot of everyday terninology at the same time.
I could add that others have their own criteria of “meaningfulness”. Humanities types aren’t very bothered about questions like how many moons saturn has, because it doens’t affect them or their society. The common factor seems to both kinds of “meaningfullness” is that they amount to “the stuff I personally consider to be worth bothering about”. A concern with objective meaningfullness is still a subjective concern.
FWIW, the Moby Dick example is less stupid than you paint it, given the recurrence of whiteness as an attribute of things special or good in western culture—an idea that pre-dates the invention of race. I think a case could be made out that (1) the causality runs from whiteness as a special or magical attribute, to its selection as a pertinent physical feature when racism was being invented (considering that there were a number of parallel candidates, like phrenology, that didn’t do so well memetically), and (2) in a world that now has racism, the ongoing presence of valuing white things as special has been both consciously used to reinforce it (cf the KKK’s name and its connotations) and unconsciously reinforces it by association,
I can’t resist. I think you should read Moby Dick. Whiteness in that novel is not used as any kind of symbol for good:
If you want to talk about racism and Moby Dick, talk about Queequeg!
Not that white animals aren’t often associated with good things, but this is not unique in western culture: