Illusion of Transparency: Why No One Understands You
In hindsight bias, people who know the outcome of a situation believe the outcome should have been easy to predict in advance. Knowing the outcome, we reinterpret the situation in light of that outcome. Even when warned, we can’t de-interpret to empathize with someone who doesn’t know what we know.
Closely related is the illusion of transparency: We always know what we mean by our words, and so we expect others to know it too. Reading our own writing, the intended interpretation falls easily into place, guided by our knowledge of what we really meant. It’s hard to empathize with someone who must interpret blindly, guided only by the words.
June recommends a restaurant to Mark; Mark dines there and discovers (a) unimpressive food and mediocre service or (b) delicious food and impeccable service. Then Mark leaves the following message on June’s answering machine: “June, I just finished dinner at the restaurant you recommended, and I must say, it was marvelous, just marvelous.” Keysar (1994) presented a group of subjects with scenario (a), and 59% thought that Mark’s message was sarcastic and that Jane would perceive the sarcasm.1 Among other subjects, told scenario (b), only 3% thought that Jane would perceive Mark’s message as sarcastic. Keysar and Barr (2002) seem to indicate that an actual voice message was played back to the subjects.2 Keysar (1998) showed that if subjects were told that the restaurant was horrible but that Mark wanted to conceal his response, they believed June would not perceive sarcasm in the (same) message:3
They were just as likely to predict that she would perceive sarcasm when he attempted to conceal his negative experience as when he had a positive experience and was truly sincere. So participants took Mark’s communicative intention as transparent. It was as if they assumed that June would perceive whatever intention Mark wanted her to perceive.4
“The goose hangs high” is an archaic English idiom that has passed out of use in modern language. Keysar and Bly (1995) told one group of subjects that “the goose hangs high” meant that the future looks good; another group of subjects learned that “the goose hangs high” meant the future looks gloomy.5 Subjects were then asked which of these two meanings an uninformed listener would be more likely to attribute to the idiom. Each group thought that listeners would perceive the meaning presented as “standard.”6
Keysar and Henly (2002) tested the calibration of speakers: Would speakers underestimate, overestimate, or correctly estimate how often listeners understood them?7 Speakers were given ambiguous sentences (“The man is chasing a woman on a bicycle.”) and disambiguating pictures (a man running after a cycling woman). Speakers were then asked to utter the words in front of addressees, and asked to estimate how many addressees understood the intended meaning. Speakers thought that they were understood in 72% of cases and were actually understood in 61% of cases. When addressees did not understand, speakers thought they did in 46% of cases; when addressees did understand, speakers thought they did not in only 12% of cases.
Additional subjects who overheard the explanation showed no such bias, expecting listeners to understand in only 56% of cases.
As Keysar and Barr note, two days before Germany’s attack on Poland, Chamberlain sent a letter intended to make it clear that Britain would fight if any invasion occurred. The letter, phrased in polite diplomatese, was heard by Hitler as conciliatory—and the tanks rolled.
Be not too quick to blame those who misunderstand your perfectly clear sentences, spoken or written. Chances are, your words are more ambiguous than you think.
1 Boaz Keysar, “The Illusory Transparency of Intention: Linguistic Perspective Taking in Text,” Cognitive Psychology 26 (2 1994): 165–208.
2 Boaz Keysar and Dale J. Barr, “Self-Anchoring in Conversation: Why Language Users Do Not Do What They ‘Should,’” in Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment, ed. Griffin Gilovich and Daniel Kahneman (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 150–166.
3 Boaz Keysar, “Language Users as Problem Solvers: Just What Ambiguity Problem Do They Solve?,” in Social and Cognitive Approaches to Interpersonal Communication, ed. Susan R. Fussell and Roger J. Kreuz (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1998), 175–200.
4 The wording here is from Keysar and Barr.
5 Boaz Keysar and Bridget Bly, “Intuitions of the Transparency of Idioms: Can One Keep a Secret by Spilling the Beans?,” Journal of Memory and Language 34 (1 1995): 89–109.
6 Other idioms tested included “come the uncle over someone,” “to go by the board,” and “to lay out in lavender.” Ah, English, such a lovely language.
7 Boaz Keysar and Anne S. Henly, “Speakers’ Overestimation of Their Effectiveness,” Psychological Science 13 (3 2002): 207–212.
- What cognitive biases feel like from the inside by 3 Jan 2020 14:24 UTC; 253 points) (
- Elements of Rationalist Discourse by 12 Feb 2023 7:58 UTC; 223 points) (
- Bayes’ Theorem Illustrated (My Way) by 3 Jun 2010 4:40 UTC; 171 points) (
- The Onion Test for Personal and Institutional Honesty by 27 Sep 2022 15:26 UTC; 162 points) (
- Double Illusion of Transparency by 24 Oct 2007 23:06 UTC; 118 points) (
- Explainers Shoot High. Aim Low! by 24 Oct 2007 1:13 UTC; 100 points) (
- A summary of every “Highlights from the Sequences” post by 15 Jul 2022 23:01 UTC; 97 points) (
- Things You Can’t Countersignal by 19 Feb 2010 0:18 UTC; 95 points) (
- EA Diversity: Unpacking Pandora’s Box by 1 Feb 2015 0:40 UTC; 89 points) (EA Forum;
- Rhetoric for the Good by 26 Oct 2011 18:52 UTC; 85 points) (
- Don’t Apply the Principle of Charity to Yourself by 19 Nov 2011 19:26 UTC; 82 points) (
- Practical Advice Backed By Deep Theories by 25 Apr 2009 18:52 UTC; 70 points) (
- Fake Utility Functions by 6 Dec 2007 16:55 UTC; 69 points) (
- Elements of Rationalist Discourse by 14 Feb 2023 3:39 UTC; 68 points) (EA Forum;
- A List of Nuances by 10 Nov 2014 5:02 UTC; 67 points) (
- Curating “The Epistemic Sequences” (list v.0.1) by 23 Jul 2022 22:17 UTC; 65 points) (
- The Onion Test for Personal and Institutional Honesty by 27 Sep 2022 15:26 UTC; 57 points) (EA Forum;
- Take heed, for it is a trap by 14 Aug 2011 10:23 UTC; 54 points) (
- Book Review: Heuristics and Biases (MIRI course list) by 2 Sep 2013 15:37 UTC; 49 points) (
- A summary of every “Highlights from the Sequences” post by 15 Jul 2022 23:05 UTC; 47 points) (EA Forum;
- Abstracted Idealized Dynamics by 12 Aug 2008 1:00 UTC; 37 points) (
- 4 Jul 2019 20:12 UTC; 36 points) 's comment on Causal Reality vs Social Reality by (
- What cognitive biases feel like from the inside by 27 Jul 2022 23:13 UTC; 33 points) (EA Forum;
- My Approach to Non-Literal Communication by 1 May 2022 2:47 UTC; 29 points) (
- An unofficial “Highlights from the Sequences” tier list by 5 Sep 2022 14:07 UTC; 29 points) (
- Reflections on applications, rejections and feedback by 28 Mar 2023 18:13 UTC; 27 points) (EA Forum;
- 9 Feb 2016 17:22 UTC; 27 points) 's comment on The Fable of the Burning Branch by (
- Moral Error and Moral Disagreement by 10 Aug 2008 23:32 UTC; 26 points) (
- The Solitaire Principle: Game Theory for One by 17 Jan 2018 0:14 UTC; 25 points) (
- Remember to translate your thoughts back again by 1 Nov 2022 8:49 UTC; 25 points) (
- 2 Jan 2012 12:09 UTC; 23 points) 's comment on For-Profit Rationality Training by (
- 3 Jun 2013 15:39 UTC; 21 points) 's comment on Open Thread, June 2-15, 2013 by (
- Help us Optimize the Contents of the Sequences eBook by 19 Sep 2013 4:31 UTC; 18 points) (
- Traversing a Cognition Space by 7 Dec 2020 18:32 UTC; 17 points) (
- Rationality Reading Group: Introduction and A: Predictably Wrong by 17 Apr 2015 1:40 UTC; 16 points) (
- Fake Amnesia by 3 Apr 2016 21:23 UTC; 16 points) (
- Chains, Bottlenecks and Optimization by 21 Jul 2020 2:07 UTC; 14 points) (
- 25 Nov 2013 1:14 UTC; 14 points) 's comment on The Craft And The Community: The Basics: Apologizing by (
- Arguing Absolute Velocities by 1 Sep 2019 2:11 UTC; 13 points) (
- 2 Oct 2011 21:20 UTC; 13 points) 's comment on Don’t ban chimp testing by (
- Whence Your Abstractions? by 20 Nov 2008 1:07 UTC; 12 points) (
- [SEQ RERUN] Illusion of Transparency: Why No One Understands You by 2 Oct 2011 3:24 UTC; 11 points) (
- 23 May 2022 10:19 UTC; 11 points) 's comment on PSA: The Sequences don’t need to be read in sequence by (
- 11 Apr 2009 23:06 UTC; 11 points) 's comment on Twelve Virtues booklet printing? by (
- 24 Jul 2009 7:39 UTC; 10 points) 's comment on Missing the Trees for the Forest by (
- 21 Jun 2013 7:38 UTC; 10 points) 's comment on What makes you different from Tim Ferriss? by (
- 22 Jun 2010 19:11 UTC; 10 points) 's comment on Poll: What value extra copies? by (
- [Pile of links] Miscommunication by 21 Feb 2012 22:02 UTC; 10 points) (
- 7 Mar 2012 15:25 UTC; 9 points) 's comment on The Fox and the Low-Hanging Grapes by (
- 8 May 2011 14:31 UTC; 9 points) 's comment on The 5-Second Level by (
- 2 May 2014 21:10 UTC; 8 points) 's comment on Rationality Quotes May 2014 by (
- 30 Nov 2012 14:16 UTC; 8 points) 's comment on LW Women- Minimizing the Inferential Distance by (
- 27 Apr 2011 21:50 UTC; 8 points) 's comment on What is Metaethics? by (
- 17 Mar 2010 11:55 UTC; 7 points) 's comment on Disconnect between Stated/Implemented Preferences by (
- 12 Aug 2010 17:48 UTC; 6 points) 's comment on Should I believe what the SIAI claims? by (
- 24 Apr 2013 22:35 UTC; 6 points) 's comment on Welcome to Less Wrong! (2012) by (
- 9 May 2011 17:49 UTC; 5 points) 's comment on The 5-Second Level by (
- 28 Jun 2013 10:42 UTC; 5 points) 's comment on Bad Concepts Repository by (
- 11 Aug 2013 2:35 UTC; 5 points) 's comment on Open thread, July 29-August 4, 2013 by (
- 10 May 2011 18:28 UTC; 5 points) 's comment on Absence of Evidence Is Evidence of Absence by (
- Como são vieses cognitivos vistos por dentro? by 20 Jul 2023 18:48 UTC; 4 points) (EA Forum;
- [Opzionale] Come percepiamo i nostri bias cognitivi by 23 Dec 2022 1:49 UTC; 4 points) (EA Forum;
- 18 Oct 2011 20:07 UTC; 4 points) 's comment on Overcoming the Curse of Knowledge by (
- 29 Sep 2009 2:37 UTC; 4 points) 's comment on The Anthropic Trilemma by (
- 22 Mar 2012 10:01 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on Harry Potter and the Methods of Rationality discussion thread, part 11 by (
- 25 Dec 2007 13:30 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on The Amazing Virgin Pregnancy by (
- 10 Jan 2014 9:31 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on We need new humans, please help by (
- 18 Feb 2010 17:36 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on Open Thread: February 2010, part 2 by (
- 19 Jul 2012 21:05 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on Challenge: change someone’s mind by (
- 22 Jun 2013 18:11 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on Rationality Quotes June 2013 by (
- 17 Jun 2016 8:35 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on Avoiding strawmen by (
- 18 Jan 2018 15:25 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on Russian Cynicism by (
- 1 Oct 2020 20:49 UTC; 2 points) 's comment on Words and Implications by (
- 1 Oct 2019 15:57 UTC; 2 points) 's comment on Feature Wish List for LessWrong by (
- 23 Jun 2013 14:47 UTC; 2 points) 's comment on Open Thread, June 16-30, 2013 by (
- 8 Apr 2015 19:54 UTC; 2 points) 's comment on Avoiding Your Belief’s Real Weak Points by (
- 10 Mar 2012 19:17 UTC; 2 points) 's comment on AI Risk and Opportunity: A Strategic Analysis by (
- 23 Mar 2009 21:07 UTC; 2 points) 's comment on Playing Video Games In Shuffle Mode by (
- 認知バイアスは内部からどのように感じられるか by 17 Jul 2023 17:14 UTC; 1 point) (EA Forum;
- 19 Jan 2011 14:04 UTC; 1 point) 's comment on Erroneous Visualizations by (
- 13 Jan 2013 18:57 UTC; 1 point) 's comment on Artificial Addition by (
- 8 Jul 2022 6:57 UTC; 1 point) 's comment on Getting from an unaligned AGI to an aligned AGI? by (
- 6 Sep 2011 7:03 UTC; 1 point) 's comment on Open Thread: September 2011 by (
- 23 Nov 2009 6:11 UTC; 1 point) 's comment on Anti-Akrasia Technique: Structured Procrastination by (
- 20 Apr 2009 23:04 UTC; 0 points) 's comment on The True Epistemic Prisoner’s Dilemma by (
- 20 Oct 2011 17:17 UTC; 0 points) 's comment on Overcoming the Curse of Knowledge by (
- 16 Apr 2011 17:01 UTC; 0 points) 's comment on Offense versus harm minimization by (
- 10 Aug 2012 10:34 UTC; 0 points) 's comment on Friendly AI and the limits of computational epistemology by (
- 1 Oct 2010 21:07 UTC; 0 points) 's comment on Open Thread September, Part 3 by (
- 10 May 2011 17:08 UTC; -2 points) 's comment on Norms survey (dead) by (
- 11 Apr 2010 20:44 UTC; -4 points) 's comment on The Trouble With “Good” by (
- Where “the Sequences” Are Wrong by 7 May 2023 20:21 UTC; -15 points) (
Google found the actual meanings of “the goose hangs high” (the future looks good), and the reason it means that (there is a goose in the larder, therefor you will not starve), and “to go by the board” (to be completely destroyed or overthrown), but not the reason behind it. What do “to come an uncle over someone” and “to lay out in lavender” mean?
‘go by the board’ is apparently of nautical derivation: http://www.phrases.org.uk/meanings/by-the-board.html http://www.io.com/gibbonsb/words.words.words.html
To “come the uncle over someone” means, according to this highly-trustworthy-looking site, to “overdo your privilege of reproving or castigating” someone.
As an example of illusion of transparency: On first reading, I interpretred your phrase ‘highly-trustworthy-looking site’ as sarcastic. Since it’s a Webster’s site, I’m going to guess that you were not intending to be sarcastic?
I think I did mean to be sarcastic, since it doesn’t seem to be actually affiliated with the publishers of Webster’s dictionary and the design of the site looks generally sketchy, but coming back to my comment now, you make a good point.
Ok, thanks for clarifying. It actually makes a lot more sense for you to be sarcastic and I read it that way at first. I only got confused once I started considering the non-sarcastic possibility.
-- Wikipedia
Ah, good to know.
I’ve heard things like this before. This is one reason why it’s a good idea to run your writing by someone else before you “publish”; you can get a better idea of whether what you wrote actually says what you wanted it to.
This is academic habit, but vulnerable to group bias. Normally, you don’t send drafts to experts who strong disagree with your statements, but close friends who wants to read what you write.
1) That’s why Deidre (then Donald) McCloskey wrote in (I believe), “The Rhetoric of Economics” (JEL 1983), that, “If the reader says something is unclear, it is unclear.” 2) The recent Rush Limbaugh imbroglio is consistent with the point about inferring meaning. The political leanings of the commentors guided their inerpretation of his words.
Humor seems the most difficult. Once I taught a guy from Sweden English. One day he read an article in the newspaper to me and could tell me what it meant—no problem. When we got to the comics page… the humor didn’t translate at all. I still don’t know why the difference was so marked.
In fairness, newpaper comics rarely have humor to translate.
Humor probably has a higher culture per word weight. (I made up this term.)
It’s because a key component of humor is someone’s status being lowered, and someone just learning the culture won’t be fluent in the status signals yet.
… sometimes. This seems like a vastly overly broad requirement for humor. First off, there are puns. Some people don’t find them to be humor, but I don’t have to look far to find a non-pun exception—I fail to see a status lowering in today’s Square Root of Minus Garfield, for instance, and even if it’s not a masterpiece, it’s somewhat funny.
I could find many other examples which only incidentally involved social status changes—Today’s xkcd is a put-down, but the relevant status (dominance of chemical elements over Greek elements) is so drastic that no appreciable further change is going to occur. Furthermore, the same joke was made much better in Order of the Stick while eliminating the put-down element.
So it seems to me that saying it’s ‘a key component’ had better not be along the lines of ‘a key ingredient’, but rather more along the lines of ‘a principal component’.
Yes, and a heavier reliance on nuances and multiple-meanings of language that come with much greater familiarity.
Certain kinds of academics use this to justify a rhetorical technique: they simply say they do not understand what you say, and they keep repeating this for any statements that do not fit with their standard method. For example, in a community uses formal statistical techniques, they say they cannot understand any argument for a probabilistic conclusion that is not expressed as a formal statistical test.
Robin, could you give a bit more detail?
I’d have to hear the voice mail message to believe what you’re saying. In my daily life, when one of my friends says, “That’s great. Just great” it’s totally clear whether he’s being sarcastic or not. Because he intends to sound sarcastic, and changes his inflection.
Now in this case the message was the same, so the inflection didn’t carry any content. But the subjects were told Mark was leaving a message for his friend. So it’s a reasonable assumption that Mark is using an inflection that his friend will recognize as sarcasm. I would assume that unless, as in the second case, they told me he was trying not to show sarcasm.
http://languagelog.ldc.upenn.edu/nll/?p=2868
(Yes, I know I’m replying to a 2007 comment with a link to a 2010 blog post.)
Totally reasonable. Unless the tone was “you’d know this if you’d only bothered to read the 2010 post first”.
Which I observed once as a comment to a post by Eliezer linking to a much-later post by Eliezer.
This only seems unreasonable to us because we haven’t yet read the 2015 post about acausal reference.
Well then that commentor should have linked to that 2015 post.
Sadly, the AHTML markup syntax won’t be available until 2017.
Still waiting.
Don’t worry, it will have been available in 2017 one of these days.
We might have missed it.
Hmm, with the proper content-based indexing...
Noumenon, one of the experiments (I think Keysar 1994) showed that, when people read in text that Mark left a voice message (that is, the experimental subjects themselves did not hear a spoken message, only read about Mark leaving one); or alternatively read in text that Mark left a written note; then they were equally likely to judge that June would identify sarcasm. In other words, the modality of text versus speech made no difference to their expectations.
Okay, then, that’s just weird. To me there’s obviously not enough information in a text message to tell sarcasm that way. Even a voice message wouldn’t be enough for someone who didn’t know Mark, like the restaurant manager.
I can’t really imagine myself in this scenario any more. My takeaway is that some people are dumb about text messages (or were in 1994 before the smiley).
If they were told Mark left a voice message, it would be rational to assume June would identify sarcasm, because it would be rational to assume that Mark left it in a sarcastic tone (or not) if he intended sarcasm (or not). Though the written note case shows that’s not what’s really going on, unfortunately.
Hi Marty here Back in the Bush we have many words to describe our environment that is mostly sand. The words are always the same but how we say the word describes what we mean example one click then word Danger under the sand maybe snake! Loud click then soft click then word slow rolling sand wind from the south face not good for hunting now. Click pop hand over our mouth then word means to hot for traveling best to go around. The word never changes or the meaning will be lost in enemy? Environment it is very important meaning is always understood life depends on meaning so I am confused about phone message Why not just say food was not good why leave meaning hanging to interpretation? This is not honest say the truth the person listening did not make the food so I say he should be honest. Or I, am I misunderstanding something in the article?
I believe the reason for saying the opposite of what you mean is so that you and your friend can say, “We’re clever. Others would not perceive our nuanced tone and would stupidly think we meant what we said.” In the bush, don’t people sometimes make the sound for “snake” when there is no snake, just so they can laugh and mock the person who foolishly believed there was a snake?
Chesh, lay out in lavender means “displayed in the best possible light” according to http://www.phrases.org.uk/meanings/222725.html. If you google “out in lavender” or “laid out in lavender”, you get more hits.
Dear Whit, yes,when there is no real danger like at a party the youngsters may play everyone knowns it is harmless. Never in the bush this would be very bad manners to frighten for a laugh beside what pleasure is gained by such unkind act to me that is a foolish game and being mean is not showing cleverness. Marty
Marty, where specifically are you from?
It should have been perfectly obvious to Julie that I was being (a) sarcastic, (b) sincere.
Talk about clever—Mark illustrates this entire post in one sentence! He points out all these readings:
It should have been perfectly obvious to Julie that I was being sarcastic. (sarcastic) It should have been perfectly obvious to Julie that I was being sarcastic. (sincere) It should have been perfectly obvious to Julie that I was being sincere. (sarcastic) It should have been perfectly obvious to Julie that I was being sincere. (sincere)
and the point of the post is that you really can’t tell from the text which way he means it or how he really felt.
From Dictionary of Phrase and Fable:
Phrasefinder says,The City in Slang: New York Life and Popular Speech by Irving Lewis Allen says that to lay out in lavender also means to pawn some good: http://books.google.com/books?id=j41z0yeKbeIC&pg=PA159&lpg=PA159
The Mark/June experiments seem flawed in that Mark and June have a pre-existing relationship that the subjects aren’t privy to. The 1994 paper you link says repeatedly that information not available to June shouldn’t affect our expectation of June’s interpretation of Mark’s message. But that’s bad Bayesianism. The other examples seem unproblematic in that we know that the subjects were being overconfident.
(below lies belaboring of this point)
Suppose we re-did the experiment, word for word, except the message went as follows:
“June, i akabad de junt lo restaurante ou você rekomendad, e devad dicher ou flo derigimedero, simplesima derigimedero.”
The correct assumption to make is that Mark is communicating successfully, since we have no other usable information. I would assign low probability that Mark is accidentally miscommunicating, and very low probability that June doesn’t speak whatever language that is.
Sarcasm between friends can be a language unto itself. My brother and I each have a vocal tone that sounds sincere to everyone else, but sarcastic to each other. I had a similar tone, my “lying voice,” that I used to signal to my college girlfriend that I was lying but that no casual acquaintance knew the meaning of. Similarly, the choice and repetition of the word marvelous signals sincerity to some pairs, signals sarcasm to others, and is ambiguous to others.
As near as I can tell from the 1994 paper, Keysar is simply missing the evidential chain: Mark’s experience at the restaurant is evidence of his intention. Mark’s intention plus his note or voicemail together constitute evidence of Mark’s model of June. Mark’s model of June is evidence of what June is actually like, and what June is actually like is evidence of how she will interpret the note.
The paper does edge tantalizingly close to acknowledging this when talking about Grice, but it still insists on calling this entirely reasonable kind of deduction an illusion.
A complete digression: it delights me that although I have no idea what language that is, I am fairly sure I understand every word in it except “derigimedoro,” which can fairly easily be classified by context. (Or, well, it could be given tone of voice, anyway.)
Which leads me to suspect it is probably Portuguese, with which I often have that relationship, although probably not Brazilian Portuguese, which I have slightly more familiarity with.
I think it would be “de regime de ouro” or in other words, a golden diet...
That’s a marvelous phrase.
“go by the board” is still in use where I come from
A recent version of this for email: http://faculty.chicagobooth.edu/nicholas.epley/Krugeretal05.pdf
This is an interesting read. Specifically, their work suggests what could be a potentially very useful way of reducing miscommunication.
One of the experiments the authors ran tried to reduce the overconfidence they saw in predicting whether people would understand or not. They asked people to write sarcastic sentances, and then read them back, out loud, in a tone of voice which made them sound completely serious. They also did serious read in a sarcastic way. They found that people were then less confident that the email would be understood in the way it was intended, because they had changed the way they “heard” it in their head.
I propose that this could be useful in the following way: if you write an email, read it aloud to yourself in the opposite tone of voice. If you are still confident that it will be taken the way you originally thought it should, it’s probably safe to send. But if you can now see how it might be misunderstood, redraft it. Repeat until you feel ready to send.
There are times in my past when this advice would have been very useful to me.
I believe this article illustrates the greatest cause of conflict on the internet.
As a person who is constantly seen as sick or rude for asking people what they mean, am glad to finally see someone who understands that a person’s words can be more ambiguos to others than that person thinks. And, to the “Don’t be too quick to blame someone for misinterpreting you.” thing, I can add: “Don’t be too quick to blame someone for asking questions.”...
About the idioms experiment: isn’t the fact that the idiom actually means say, that the future looks good, evidence that an uninformed person would think it means that? Because, whatever you originally thought it meant, there might be some logical reason for its actual meaning, which you missed. So is it possible that the subjects were being rational?
The subjects that were told “the goose hangs high” mean the future looks gloomy believe the standard interpretation is the future looks gloomy. So no, it is not evidence that the most subjects were being rational. In fact it shows that most people are fallible to this bias.
If we were given more information though, such as 80% of ‘looks good’ subjects think that the standard interpretation is ‘look good’, while only 60% of ‘looks gloomy’ subjects think the standard interpretation is ‘looks gloomy’, then it is an evidence that SOME subjects are rational.