[Written September 02, 2022. Note: I’m likely to not respond to comments promptly.]
Sometimes people defer to other people, e.g. by believing what they say, by following orders, or by adopting intents or stances. In many cases it makes sense to defer, since other people know more than you about many things, and it’s useful to share eyes and ears, and coordination and specialization are valuable, and one can “inquisitively defer” to opinions by taking them as challenges to investigate further by trying them out for oneself. But there are major issues with deferring, among which are:
Deferral-based opinions don’t contain the detailed content that generated the opinions, and therefore can’t direct action effectively or update on new evidence correctly.
Acting based on deferral-based opinions is discouraging because it’s especially not the case that the whole of you can see why the action is good.
Acting based on deferral-based opinions to some extent removes the “meaning” of learning new information; if you’re just going to defer anyway, it’s sort of irrelevant to gain information, and your brain can kind of tell that, so you don’t seek information as much. Deference therefore constricts the influx of new information to individuals and groups.
A group with many people deferring to others will amplify information cascades by double-triple-quadruple-counting non-deferral-based evidence.
A group with many people deferring to others will have mistakenly correlated beliefs and actions, and so will fail to explore many worthwhile possibilities.
The deferrer will copy beliefs mistakenly imputed to the deferred-to that would have explained the deferred-to’s externally visible behavior. This pushes in the direction opposite to science because science is the way of making beliefs come apart from their pre-theoretical pragmatic implications.
Sometimes the deferrer, instead of imputing beliefs to the deferred-to and adopting those beliefs, will adopt the same model-free behavioral stance that the deferred-to has adopted to perform to onlookers, such as pretending to believe something while acting towards no coherent purpose other than to maintain the pretense.
If the deferred-to takes actions for PR reasons, e.g. attempting to appear from the outside to hold some belief or intent that they don’t actually hold, then the PR might work on the deferrer so that the deferrer systematically adopts the false beliefs and non-held intents performed by the deferred-to (rather than adopting beliefs and intents that would actually explain the deferred-to’s actions as part of a coherent worldview and strategy).
Allocating resources based on deferral-based opinions potentially opens up niches for non-epistemic processes, such as hype, fraud, and power-grabbing.
These dynamics will be amplified when people choose who to defer to according to how much the person is already being deferred to.
To the extent that these dynamics increase the general orientation of deference itself, deference recursively amplifies itself.
Together, these dynamics make it so that deferral-based opinions are under strong pressure to not function as actual beliefs that can be used to make successful plans and can be ongoingly updated to track reality. So I recommend that people
keep these dynamics in mind when deferring,
track the difference between believing someone’s testimony vs. deferring to beliefs imputed to someone based on their actions vs. adopting non-belief performative stances, and
give substantial parliamentary decision-weight to the recommendations made by their expectations about facts-on-the-ground that they can see with their own eyes.
Not to throw away arguments or information from other people, or to avoid investigating important-if-true claims, but to think as though thinking matters.
Dangers of deference
[Written September 02, 2022. Note: I’m likely to not respond to comments promptly.]
Sometimes people defer to other people, e.g. by believing what they say, by following orders, or by adopting intents or stances. In many cases it makes sense to defer, since other people know more than you about many things, and it’s useful to share eyes and ears, and coordination and specialization are valuable, and one can “inquisitively defer” to opinions by taking them as challenges to investigate further by trying them out for oneself. But there are major issues with deferring, among which are:
Deferral-based opinions don’t contain the detailed content that generated the opinions, and therefore can’t direct action effectively or update on new evidence correctly.
Acting based on deferral-based opinions is discouraging because it’s especially not the case that the whole of you can see why the action is good.
Acting based on deferral-based opinions to some extent removes the “meaning” of learning new information; if you’re just going to defer anyway, it’s sort of irrelevant to gain information, and your brain can kind of tell that, so you don’t seek information as much. Deference therefore constricts the influx of new information to individuals and groups.
A group with many people deferring to others will amplify information cascades by double-triple-quadruple-counting non-deferral-based evidence.
A group with many people deferring to others will have mistakenly correlated beliefs and actions, and so will fail to explore many worthwhile possibilities.
The deferrer will copy beliefs mistakenly imputed to the deferred-to that would have explained the deferred-to’s externally visible behavior. This pushes in the direction opposite to science because science is the way of making beliefs come apart from their pre-theoretical pragmatic implications.
Sometimes the deferrer, instead of imputing beliefs to the deferred-to and adopting those beliefs, will adopt the same model-free behavioral stance that the deferred-to has adopted to perform to onlookers, such as pretending to believe something while acting towards no coherent purpose other than to maintain the pretense.
If the deferred-to takes actions for PR reasons, e.g. attempting to appear from the outside to hold some belief or intent that they don’t actually hold, then the PR might work on the deferrer so that the deferrer systematically adopts the false beliefs and non-held intents performed by the deferred-to (rather than adopting beliefs and intents that would actually explain the deferred-to’s actions as part of a coherent worldview and strategy).
Allocating resources based on deferral-based opinions potentially opens up niches for non-epistemic processes, such as hype, fraud, and power-grabbing.
These dynamics will be amplified when people choose who to defer to according to how much the person is already being deferred to.
To the extent that these dynamics increase the general orientation of deference itself, deference recursively amplifies itself.
Together, these dynamics make it so that deferral-based opinions are under strong pressure to not function as actual beliefs that can be used to make successful plans and can be ongoingly updated to track reality. So I recommend that people
keep these dynamics in mind when deferring,
track the difference between believing someone’s testimony vs. deferring to beliefs imputed to someone based on their actions vs. adopting non-belief performative stances, and
give substantial parliamentary decision-weight to the recommendations made by their expectations about facts-on-the-ground that they can see with their own eyes.
Not to throw away arguments or information from other people, or to avoid investigating important-if-true claims, but to think as though thinking matters.