However, though dominance is hard-coded, it seems like something of a simple evolved hack to avoid costly fights among relatively low-cognitive-capability agents; it does not seem like the sort of thing which more capable agents (like e.g. future AI, or even future more-intelligent humans) would rely on very heavily.
This seems exactly reversed to me. It seems to me that since dominance underlies defense, law, taxes and public expenditure, it will stay crucial even with more intelligent agents. Conversely, as intelligence becomes “too cheap to meter”, “getting what you want” will become less bottlenecked on relevant insights, as those insights are always available.
It seems to me that the importance and interaction of these different types of power in the future depends a lot on our choices now, ie, what kind of future we shape. Hierarchies could get smashed in one way or another, making John’s prediction correct, or we could engineer a future that evolves from the present more smoothly, in which case you’d be correct.
Hierarchies getting smashed requires someone to smash them, in which case that someone has the mandate of heaven. That’s how it worked with John Wentworth’s original example of Zhu Di, who overthrew Zhu Yunwen.
If they’re being smashed in a literal sense, sure. I think the more likely way things would go is that hierarchies just cease to be a stable equilibrium arrangement. For instance, if the bulk of economic activity shifts (either quickly or slowly) to AIs and those AIs coordinate mostly non-hierarchically amongst themselves.
A monopoly on violence is not the only way to coordinate such things—even among humans, at small-to-medium scale we often rely on norms and reputation rather than an explicit enforcer with a monopoly on violence. The reason those mechanisms don’t scale well for humans seems to be (at least in part) that human cognition is tuned for Dunbar’s number.
And even if a monopoly on violence does turn out to be (part of) the convergent way to coordinate, that’s not-at-all synonymous with a dominance hierarchy. For instance, one could imagine the prototypical libertarian paradise in which a government with monopoly on violence enforces property rights and contracts but otherwise leaves people to interact as they please. In that world, there’s one layer of dominance, but no further hierarchy beneath. That one layer is a useful foundational tool for coordination, but most of the day-to-day work of coordinating can then happen via other mechanisms (like e.g. markets).
(I suspect that a government which was just greedy for resources would converge to an arrangement roughly like that, with moderate taxes on property and/or contracts. The reason we don’t see that happen in our world is mostly, I claim, that the humans who run governments usually aren’t just greedy for resources, and instead have a strong craving for dominance as an approximately-terminal goal.)
Given a world of humans, I don’t think that libertarian society would be good enough at preventing competing powers from overthrowing it. Because there’d be an unexploitable-equillibrium condition where a government that isn’t focused on dominance is weaker than a government more focused on government, it would generally be held by those who have the strongest focus on dominance. Those who desire resources would be better off putting themselves in situations where the dominant powers can become more dominant by giving them/putting them in charge of resources.
Given a world of AIs, I don’t think the dominant AI would need a market; it could just handle everything itself.
As I understand it, libertarian paradises are basically fantasies by people who don’t like the government, not realistically-achievable outcomes given the political realities.
Because there’d be an unexploitable-equillibrium condition where a government that isn’t focused on dominance is weaker than a government more focused on government, it would generally be held by those who have the strongest focus on dominance.
This argument only works insofar as governments less focused on dominance are, in fact, weaker militarily, which seems basically-false in practice in the long run. For instance, autocratic regimes just can’t compete industrially with a market economy like e.g. most Western states today, and that industrial difference turns into a comprehensive military advantage with relatively moderate time and investment. And when countries switch to full autocracy, there’s sometimes a short-term military buildup but they tend to end up waaaay behind militarily a few years down the road IIUC.
Maybe one could say the essence of our difference is this:
You see the dominance ranking as defined by the backing-off tendency and assume it to be mainly an evolutionary psychological artifact.
Meanwhile, I see the backing-off tendency as being the primary indicator of dominance, but the core interesting aspect of dominance to be the tendency to leverage credible threats, which of course causes but is not equivalent to the psychological tendency to back off.
Under my model, dominance would then be able to cause bargaining power (e.g. robbing someone by threatening to shoot them), but one could also use bargaining power to purchase dominance (e.g. spending money to purchase a gun).
This leaves dominance and bargaining power independent because on the one hand you have the weak-strong axis where both increase but on the other hand you have the merchant-king axis where they directly trade off.
I guess to expand, the US military doctrine since the world war has been that there’s a need to maintain dominance over countries focused on military strength to the disadvantage of their citizens. Hence while your statement is somewhat-true, it’s directly and intentionally the result of a dominance hierarchy maintained by the US.
Western states today use state violence to enforce high taxes and lots of government regulations. In my view they’re probably more dominance-oriented than states which just leave rural farmers alone. At least some of this is part of a Keynesian policy to boost economic output, and economic output is closely related to military formidability (due to ability to afford raw resources and advanced technology for the military).
Hm, I guess you would see this as more closely related to bargaining power than to dominance, because in your model dominance is a human-psychology-thing and bargaining power isn’t restricted to voluntary transactions?
Good guess, but that’s not cruxy for me. Yes, LDT/FDT-style things are one possibility. But even if those fail, I still expect non-hierarchical coordination mechanisms among highly capable agents.
Gesturing more at where the intuition comes from: compare hierarchical management to markets, as a control mechanism. Markets require clean factorization—a production problem needs to be factored into production of standardized, verifiable intermediate goods in order for markets to handle the production pipeline well. If that can be done, then markets scale very well, they pass exactly the information and incentives people need (in the form of prices). Hierarchies, in contrast, scale very poorly. They provide basically-zero built-in mechanisms for passing the right information between agents, or for providing precise incentives to each agent. They’re the sort of thing which can work ok at small scale, where the person at the top can track everything going on everywhere, but quickly become extremely bottlenecked on the top person as you scale up. And you can see this pretty clearly at real-world companies: past a very small size, companies are usually extremely bottlenecked on the attention of top executives, because lower-level people lack the incentives/information to coordinate on their own across different parts of the company.
(Now, you might think that an AI in charge of e.g. a company could make the big hierarchy work efficiently by just being capable enough to track everything themselves. But at that point, I wouldn’t expect to see an hierarchy at all; the AI can just do everything itself and not have multiple agents in the first place. Unlike humans, AIs will not be limited by their number of hands. If there is to be some arrangement involving multiple agents coordinating in the first place, then it shouldn’t be possible for one mind to just do everything itself.)
On the other hand, while dominance relations scale very poorly as a coordination mechanism, they are algorithmically relatively simple. Thus my claim from the post that dominance seems like a hack for low-capability agents, and higher-capability agents will mostly rely on some other coordination mechanism.
(Now, you might think that an AI in charge of e.g. a company could make the big hierarchy work efficiently by just being capable enough to track everything themselves. But at that point, I wouldn’t expect to see an hierarchy at all; the AI can just do everything itself and not have multiple agents in the first place. Unlike humans, AIs will not be limited by their number of hands. If there is to be some arrangement involving multiple agents coordinating in the first place, then it shouldn’t be possible for one mind to just do everything itself.)
My model probably mostly resembles this situation. Some ~singular AI will maintain a monopoly on violence. Maybe it will use all the resources in the solar system, leaving no space for anyone else. Alternatively (for instance if alignment succeeds), it will leave one or more sources of resources that other agents can use. If the dominant AI fully protects these smaller agents from each other, then they’ll handle their basic preferences and mostly withdraw into their own world, ending the hierarchy. If the dominant AI has some preference for who to favor, or leaves some options for aggression/exploitation which don’t threaten the dominant AI, then someone is going to win this fight, making the hierarchy repeat fractally down.
Main complication to this model is inertia; if human property rights are preserved well enough, then most resources would start out owned by humans, and it would take some time for the economy to equillibrate to the above.
Maybe, but I’m not sure it’s even necessary to invoke LDT/FDT/UDT, and instead argue that coordinating even through solely causal methods is very cheap for AIs to the point where coordination, and as a side effect, interfaces become quite a lot less of a bottleneck compared to today.
In essence, I think the diff between John’s models and tailcalled’s models is plausibly in how easy coordination in a more general sense can ever be for AIs, and whether AIs have much better ability to coordinate compared to humans today, where John thinks that coordination is a taut constraint for humans but not for AI, but tailcalled thinks it’s hard to coordinate for both AIs and humans due to fundamental limits.
Dominance underlies the things that can be done most efficiently with dominance. The moment dominance is no longer the most efficient force, it collapses, because in the vast majority of cases, dominating others takes a lot of time, energy and effort. This is actually how and why slavery (pretty much the most powerful example of dominance) was abolished: it started to make less economic sense than Bargaining (paid employment of freemen) and just Getting Things Done (through better tools and ultimately machines), so even its most ardent supporters became dispirited.
Slavery was abolished and remains abolished through dominance:
first by getting outlawed by the Northern US and Great Britain, who drew strong economic benefit from higher labor prices due to them industrializing earlier for geographic reasons,
secondly by leveraging state dominance during the great depression to demand massive increases in quality and quantity of production, to make it feasible to maintain a non-slave-holding society without having excess labor forces being forced to starve,
thirdly, endless policies that use state violence and reduce the total fertility rate as a side-effect,
Throughout most of history, there has been excess labor, making the value of work fall down close to the cost of subsistence, being only sustainable because landowners see natural fluctuations in their production and therefore desire to keep people around even if it doesn’t make short-term economic sense. This naturally creates serfdom and indentured servitude.
It’s only really prisoners of war (e.g. African-American chattel slaves) who are slaves due to dominance; ordinary slavery is just poor bargaining power.
The current number for slaves in the world in something like 50 million. It’s a significant amount of people. In prostitution, you unfortunately have women that are enslaved with violence and other forms of dominance that are not just about the poor bargaining power of the prostitutes.
I didn’t ask where the number is from, I asked how they came up with that number. Their official definition is “all work or service which is exacted from any person under the menace
of any penalty and for which the said person has not offered himself voluntarily”, but taking that literally would seem to imply that additional work to pay taxes is slavery and therefore ~everyone is a slave. This is presumably not what they meant, and indeed it’s inconsistent with their actual number, but it’s unclear what they mean instead.
I consider it worthwhile to provide sources so that you can read their methodology yourself. I don’t see a good reason for me to give you my interpretation of their methodology.
Your link doesn’t contain a detailed description of their methodology or intermediate results. I would have to do a lot of digging to make heads or tails of it.
I guess feel free to opt out of this conversation if you want but then ultimately I don’t see you as having contributed any point that is relevant for me to respond to or update with.
The key issue I raised was not about the exact number but about prostitutes not being prisoners of war and still better modeled as slaves due to dominance than slaves due to poor bargaining power.
Your sources are not very clear about that, and it contradicts what I’ve heard elsewhere, but yes I do admit at the boundaries of where society enforces laws, there do exist people who are forced to do things including prostitution via dominance.
I was once talking with someone who in the past was thinking about opening a brothel and who had some insight about how brothels are run in Germany and who said that a lot of coercion is used.
Recently, I read something from a policeman who was complaining about how the standard of proving coercion for prostitutes is too high. Proving that a prostitute who’s over 21 who left was beaten was not enough in court to convince the court that she falls under the criteria of outlawed exploitation of prostitutions.
I don’t really have any end-to-end narrative, but here’s a bunch of opinion-fragments:
There’s lots of good reason to believe that sometimes there’s dominance-based prostitution. However, all the prostitutes I’ve talked with on these subjects have emphasized that there’s a powerful alliance between prudish leftists and religious people who misrepresent what’s really going on in order to marginalize prostitution, so I’m still inclined to hold your claims to especially high standards, and I don’t really know why you (apparently) trust the organizations that prostitutes oppose so much.
Der Speigel does not describe how they sampled the individual stories they ended up with, and it seems very unlikely that they sampled them the same way that the UN number did, so it doesn’t seem like the UN number should be assumed to reflect stories like the ones in Der Speigel.
The article has multiple mentions of women who left prostitution but then later returned. In one of them, it’s for the pay, which seems like a bargaining power issue (unless we go into the mess of counting taxes). In another, it’s more complicated as it was out of hope that a customer would fall in love with her. (Which seems unlikely to happen? Would maybe count as something similar to the vaccine situation, insight into how to achieve one’s goals.)
In the case of e.g. Alina, it sounds like the main form of dominance was dominance by proxy: “She says that she was hardly ever beaten, nor were the other women. “They said that they knew enough people in Romania who knew where our families lived. That was enough,” says Alina.”. This matches my proposal about how the dominance needs to occur at the boundary of where the law can enforce.
This sounds very suspicious to me: “There are many women from EU countries “whose situation suggests they are the victims of human trafficking, but it is difficult to provide proof that would hold up in court,” reads the BKA report. Everything depends on the women’s testimony, the authors write, but there is “little willingness to cooperate with the police and assistance agencies, especially in the case of presumed victims from Romania and Bulgaria.”″
I gave you three sources that are influential to my views. A Spiegel article, a conversation with someone who in the past was planning to run a brothel (and spoke with people who actually run brothels in Germany for that reason) and police sources.
I did not link to some activist NGO run by prudish leftists or religious people or making claims as a reason for me believing what I believe.
In general, it’s hard to know what’s actually going on when it comes to crime. If you spoke in the 1950s about the Italian mafia, you had plenty of people calling you racist against Italians and say that there’s no mafia.
Clarifying question: If A>B on the dominance hierarchy, that doesn’t seem to mean that A can always just take all B’s stuff, per the Emperor of China example. It also doesn’t mean that A can trust B to act faithfully as A’s agent, per the cowpox example.
If all dominance hierarchies control is who has to signal submission to whom, dominance seems only marginally useful for defense, law, taxes, and public expenditure; mostly as a way of reducing friction toward the outcome that would have happened anyway.
It seems like, with intelligence too cheap to meter, any dominance hierarchy that doesn’t line up well with the bargaining power hierarchy or the getting-what-you-want vector space is going to be populated with nothing but scheming viziers.
But that seems like a silly conclusion, so I think I’m missing something about dominance hierarchies.
I think John Wentworth and I are modelling it in different ways and that may be the root of your confusion. To me, dominance is something like the credible ability and willingness to impose costs targeted at particular agents, whereas John Wentworth is more using the submission signalling definition.
Your definition seems like it fits the Emperor of China example—by reputation, they had few competitors for being the most willing and able to pessimize another agent’s utility function; e.g. 9 Familial Exterminations. And that seems to be a key to understanding this type of power, because if they were able to pessimize all other agents’ utility functions, that would just be an evil mirror of bargaining power. Being able to choose a sharply limited number of unfortunate agents, and punish them severely pour encourager les autres, seems like it might just stop working when the average agent is smart enough to implicitly coordinate around a shared understanding of payoff matrices. So I think I might have arrived back to the “all dominance hierarchies will be populated solely by scheming viziers” conclusion.
This seems exactly reversed to me. It seems to me that since dominance underlies defense, law, taxes and public expenditure, it will stay crucial even with more intelligent agents. Conversely, as intelligence becomes “too cheap to meter”, “getting what you want” will become less bottlenecked on relevant insights, as those insights are always available.
It seems to me that the importance and interaction of these different types of power in the future depends a lot on our choices now, ie, what kind of future we shape. Hierarchies could get smashed in one way or another, making John’s prediction correct, or we could engineer a future that evolves from the present more smoothly, in which case you’d be correct.
Hierarchies getting smashed requires someone to smash them, in which case that someone has the mandate of heaven. That’s how it worked with John Wentworth’s original example of Zhu Di, who overthrew Zhu Yunwen.
If they’re being smashed in a literal sense, sure. I think the more likely way things would go is that hierarchies just cease to be a stable equilibrium arrangement. For instance, if the bulk of economic activity shifts (either quickly or slowly) to AIs and those AIs coordinate mostly non-hierarchically amongst themselves.
I would expect the AI society to need some sort of monopoly on violence to coordinate this, which is basically the same as a dominance hierarchy.
A monopoly on violence is not the only way to coordinate such things—even among humans, at small-to-medium scale we often rely on norms and reputation rather than an explicit enforcer with a monopoly on violence. The reason those mechanisms don’t scale well for humans seems to be (at least in part) that human cognition is tuned for Dunbar’s number.
And even if a monopoly on violence does turn out to be (part of) the convergent way to coordinate, that’s not-at-all synonymous with a dominance hierarchy. For instance, one could imagine the prototypical libertarian paradise in which a government with monopoly on violence enforces property rights and contracts but otherwise leaves people to interact as they please. In that world, there’s one layer of dominance, but no further hierarchy beneath. That one layer is a useful foundational tool for coordination, but most of the day-to-day work of coordinating can then happen via other mechanisms (like e.g. markets).
(I suspect that a government which was just greedy for resources would converge to an arrangement roughly like that, with moderate taxes on property and/or contracts. The reason we don’t see that happen in our world is mostly, I claim, that the humans who run governments usually aren’t just greedy for resources, and instead have a strong craving for dominance as an approximately-terminal goal.)
Given a world of humans, I don’t think that libertarian society would be good enough at preventing competing powers from overthrowing it. Because there’d be an unexploitable-equillibrium condition where a government that isn’t focused on dominance is weaker than a government more focused on government, it would generally be held by those who have the strongest focus on dominance. Those who desire resources would be better off putting themselves in situations where the dominant powers can become more dominant by giving them/putting them in charge of resources.
Given a world of AIs, I don’t think the dominant AI would need a market; it could just handle everything itself.
As I understand it, libertarian paradises are basically fantasies by people who don’t like the government, not realistically-achievable outcomes given the political realities.
This argument only works insofar as governments less focused on dominance are, in fact, weaker militarily, which seems basically-false in practice in the long run. For instance, autocratic regimes just can’t compete industrially with a market economy like e.g. most Western states today, and that industrial difference turns into a comprehensive military advantage with relatively moderate time and investment. And when countries switch to full autocracy, there’s sometimes a short-term military buildup but they tend to end up waaaay behind militarily a few years down the road IIUC.
Maybe one could say the essence of our difference is this:
You see the dominance ranking as defined by the backing-off tendency and assume it to be mainly an evolutionary psychological artifact.
Meanwhile, I see the backing-off tendency as being the primary indicator of dominance, but the core interesting aspect of dominance to be the tendency to leverage credible threats, which of course causes but is not equivalent to the psychological tendency to back off.
Under my model, dominance would then be able to cause bargaining power (e.g. robbing someone by threatening to shoot them), but one could also use bargaining power to purchase dominance (e.g. spending money to purchase a gun).
This leaves dominance and bargaining power independent because on the one hand you have the weak-strong axis where both increase but on the other hand you have the merchant-king axis where they directly trade off.
I guess to expand, the US military doctrine since the world war has been that there’s a need to maintain dominance over countries focused on military strength to the disadvantage of their citizens. Hence while your statement is somewhat-true, it’s directly and intentionally the result of a dominance hierarchy maintained by the US.
Western states today use state violence to enforce high taxes and lots of government regulations. In my view they’re probably more dominance-oriented than states which just leave rural farmers alone. At least some of this is part of a Keynesian policy to boost economic output, and economic output is closely related to military formidability (due to ability to afford raw resources and advanced technology for the military).
Hm, I guess you would see this as more closely related to bargaining power than to dominance, because in your model dominance is a human-psychology-thing and bargaining power isn’t restricted to voluntary transactions?
I am going to guess that the diff between you and John’s models here is that John thinks LDT/FDT solves this, and you don’t.
Good guess, but that’s not cruxy for me. Yes, LDT/FDT-style things are one possibility. But even if those fail, I still expect non-hierarchical coordination mechanisms among highly capable agents.
Gesturing more at where the intuition comes from: compare hierarchical management to markets, as a control mechanism. Markets require clean factorization—a production problem needs to be factored into production of standardized, verifiable intermediate goods in order for markets to handle the production pipeline well. If that can be done, then markets scale very well, they pass exactly the information and incentives people need (in the form of prices). Hierarchies, in contrast, scale very poorly. They provide basically-zero built-in mechanisms for passing the right information between agents, or for providing precise incentives to each agent. They’re the sort of thing which can work ok at small scale, where the person at the top can track everything going on everywhere, but quickly become extremely bottlenecked on the top person as you scale up. And you can see this pretty clearly at real-world companies: past a very small size, companies are usually extremely bottlenecked on the attention of top executives, because lower-level people lack the incentives/information to coordinate on their own across different parts of the company.
(Now, you might think that an AI in charge of e.g. a company could make the big hierarchy work efficiently by just being capable enough to track everything themselves. But at that point, I wouldn’t expect to see an hierarchy at all; the AI can just do everything itself and not have multiple agents in the first place. Unlike humans, AIs will not be limited by their number of hands. If there is to be some arrangement involving multiple agents coordinating in the first place, then it shouldn’t be possible for one mind to just do everything itself.)
On the other hand, while dominance relations scale very poorly as a coordination mechanism, they are algorithmically relatively simple. Thus my claim from the post that dominance seems like a hack for low-capability agents, and higher-capability agents will mostly rely on some other coordination mechanism.
My model probably mostly resembles this situation. Some ~singular AI will maintain a monopoly on violence. Maybe it will use all the resources in the solar system, leaving no space for anyone else. Alternatively (for instance if alignment succeeds), it will leave one or more sources of resources that other agents can use. If the dominant AI fully protects these smaller agents from each other, then they’ll handle their basic preferences and mostly withdraw into their own world, ending the hierarchy. If the dominant AI has some preference for who to favor, or leaves some options for aggression/exploitation which don’t threaten the dominant AI, then someone is going to win this fight, making the hierarchy repeat fractally down.
Main complication to this model is inertia; if human property rights are preserved well enough, then most resources would start out owned by humans, and it would take some time for the economy to equillibrate to the above.
Maybe, but I’m not sure it’s even necessary to invoke LDT/FDT/UDT, and instead argue that coordinating even through solely causal methods is very cheap for AIs to the point where coordination, and as a side effect, interfaces become quite a lot less of a bottleneck compared to today.
In essence, I think the diff between John’s models and tailcalled’s models is plausibly in how easy coordination in a more general sense can ever be for AIs, and whether AIs have much better ability to coordinate compared to humans today, where John thinks that coordination is a taut constraint for humans but not for AI, but tailcalled thinks it’s hard to coordinate for both AIs and humans due to fundamental limits.
LDT/FDT is a central example of rationalist-Gnostic heresy.
Dominance underlies the things that can be done most efficiently with dominance. The moment dominance is no longer the most efficient force, it collapses, because in the vast majority of cases, dominating others takes a lot of time, energy and effort. This is actually how and why slavery (pretty much the most powerful example of dominance) was abolished: it started to make less economic sense than Bargaining (paid employment of freemen) and just Getting Things Done (through better tools and ultimately machines), so even its most ardent supporters became dispirited.
Slavery was abolished and remains abolished through dominance:
first by getting outlawed by the Northern US and Great Britain, who drew strong economic benefit from higher labor prices due to them industrializing earlier for geographic reasons,
secondly by leveraging state dominance during the great depression to demand massive increases in quality and quantity of production, to make it feasible to maintain a non-slave-holding society without having excess labor forces being forced to starve,
thirdly, endless policies that use state violence and reduce the total fertility rate as a side-effect,
Throughout most of history, there has been excess labor, making the value of work fall down close to the cost of subsistence, being only sustainable because landowners see natural fluctuations in their production and therefore desire to keep people around even if it doesn’t make short-term economic sense. This naturally creates serfdom and indentured servitude.
It’s only really prisoners of war (e.g. African-American chattel slaves) who are slaves due to dominance; ordinary slavery is just poor bargaining power.
The current number for slaves in the world in something like 50 million. It’s a significant amount of people. In prostitution, you unfortunately have women that are enslaved with violence and other forms of dominance that are not just about the poor bargaining power of the prostitutes.
Can you expand on the methodology behind this number?
The number is from the International Labour Organization of the UN.
I didn’t ask where the number is from, I asked how they came up with that number. Their official definition is “all work or service which is exacted from any person under the menace of any penalty and for which the said person has not offered himself voluntarily”, but taking that literally would seem to imply that additional work to pay taxes is slavery and therefore ~everyone is a slave. This is presumably not what they meant, and indeed it’s inconsistent with their actual number, but it’s unclear what they mean instead.
I consider it worthwhile to provide sources so that you can read their methodology yourself. I don’t see a good reason for me to give you my interpretation of their methodology.
Your link doesn’t contain a detailed description of their methodology or intermediate results. I would have to do a lot of digging to make heads or tails of it.
I guess feel free to opt out of this conversation if you want but then ultimately I don’t see you as having contributed any point that is relevant for me to respond to or update with.
The key issue I raised was not about the exact number but about prostitutes not being prisoners of war and still better modeled as slaves due to dominance than slaves due to poor bargaining power.
Your sources are not very clear about that, and it contradicts what I’ve heard elsewhere, but yes I do admit at the boundaries of where society enforces laws, there do exist people who are forced to do things including prostitution via dominance.
If we take the issue of forced prostitution and the official numbers are estimates and by their nature estimates are not exact.
https://www.spiegel.de/international/germany/human-trafficking-persists-despite-legality-of-prostitution-in-germany-a-902533.html would be a journalistic story about prostitution in Germany that describes what happens here with legalized prostitution.
I was once talking with someone who in the past was thinking about opening a brothel and who had some insight about how brothels are run in Germany and who said that a lot of coercion is used.
Recently, I read something from a policeman who was complaining about how the standard of proving coercion for prostitutes is too high. Proving that a prostitute who’s over 21 who left was beaten was not enough in court to convince the court that she falls under the criteria of outlawed exploitation of prostitutions.
I don’t really have any end-to-end narrative, but here’s a bunch of opinion-fragments:
There’s lots of good reason to believe that sometimes there’s dominance-based prostitution. However, all the prostitutes I’ve talked with on these subjects have emphasized that there’s a powerful alliance between prudish leftists and religious people who misrepresent what’s really going on in order to marginalize prostitution, so I’m still inclined to hold your claims to especially high standards, and I don’t really know why you (apparently) trust the organizations that prostitutes oppose so much.
Der Speigel does not describe how they sampled the individual stories they ended up with, and it seems very unlikely that they sampled them the same way that the UN number did, so it doesn’t seem like the UN number should be assumed to reflect stories like the ones in Der Speigel.
The article has multiple mentions of women who left prostitution but then later returned. In one of them, it’s for the pay, which seems like a bargaining power issue (unless we go into the mess of counting taxes). In another, it’s more complicated as it was out of hope that a customer would fall in love with her. (Which seems unlikely to happen? Would maybe count as something similar to the vaccine situation, insight into how to achieve one’s goals.)
In the case of e.g. Alina, it sounds like the main form of dominance was dominance by proxy: “She says that she was hardly ever beaten, nor were the other women. “They said that they knew enough people in Romania who knew where our families lived. That was enough,” says Alina.”. This matches my proposal about how the dominance needs to occur at the boundary of where the law can enforce.
This sounds very suspicious to me: “There are many women from EU countries “whose situation suggests they are the victims of human trafficking, but it is difficult to provide proof that would hold up in court,” reads the BKA report. Everything depends on the women’s testimony, the authors write, but there is “little willingness to cooperate with the police and assistance agencies, especially in the case of presumed victims from Romania and Bulgaria.”″
I gave you three sources that are influential to my views. A Spiegel article, a conversation with someone who in the past was planning to run a brothel (and spoke with people who actually run brothels in Germany for that reason) and police sources.
I did not link to some activist NGO run by prudish leftists or religious people or making claims as a reason for me believing what I believe.
In general, it’s hard to know what’s actually going on when it comes to crime. If you spoke in the 1950s about the Italian mafia, you had plenty of people calling you racist against Italians and say that there’s no mafia.
Clarifying question: If A>B on the dominance hierarchy, that doesn’t seem to mean that A can always just take all B’s stuff, per the Emperor of China example. It also doesn’t mean that A can trust B to act faithfully as A’s agent, per the cowpox example.
If all dominance hierarchies control is who has to signal submission to whom, dominance seems only marginally useful for defense, law, taxes, and public expenditure; mostly as a way of reducing friction toward the outcome that would have happened anyway.
It seems like, with intelligence too cheap to meter, any dominance hierarchy that doesn’t line up well with the bargaining power hierarchy or the getting-what-you-want vector space is going to be populated with nothing but scheming viziers.
But that seems like a silly conclusion, so I think I’m missing something about dominance hierarchies.
I think John Wentworth and I are modelling it in different ways and that may be the root of your confusion. To me, dominance is something like the credible ability and willingness to impose costs targeted at particular agents, whereas John Wentworth is more using the submission signalling definition.
Your definition seems like it fits the Emperor of China example—by reputation, they had few competitors for being the most willing and able to pessimize another agent’s utility function; e.g. 9 Familial Exterminations.
And that seems to be a key to understanding this type of power, because if they were able to pessimize all other agents’ utility functions, that would just be an evil mirror of bargaining power. Being able to choose a sharply limited number of unfortunate agents, and punish them severely pour encourager les autres, seems like it might just stop working when the average agent is smart enough to implicitly coordinate around a shared understanding of payoff matrices.
So I think I might have arrived back to the “all dominance hierarchies will be populated solely by scheming viziers” conclusion.
Can you explain what this coordination would look like?
I think that conclusion is basically correct.