But you must mean that ‘theories take account of observations, past and present’ since no theory should have to match my observation of a bent stick.
Again, you have to remember that your ‘observation of a bent stick’ does not match all of the observations we have for bent sticks. If you put your fingers in the water and felt the stick bend, you would conclude that water bends sticks.
That’s not the work that Egan’s law seems to do in, say, “Living in Many Worlds”.
I don’t speak for EY, but I will try to answer:
First, in that particular quote, I hold that to be a promisary note (one that you might not feel he delivered on) that once you are done reading, it shouldn’t conflict with your normal intuitions. That said, I will try to answer your more specific worry.
QM’s straightforward reading endorses a many-world thesis, or something much like it. One can attempt to reject MW because we do not experience this “splitting,” or because it breaks down their notions of personal identity, or because they are unclear how it should alter their planning.
Saying that ‘It all adds up to normality’ here doesn’t mean that your intuitions about, say, personal identity can’t or shouldn’t change on the basis of what you learn about QM or MW. What it means is that if you suddenly conclude something like ”… so we don’t exist” either you made an error somewhere or the theory is wrong.
Let me try to make this more concrete: Say that I decide that because of QM and MW, that buckling my seatbelt and driving safely is either useless (quantum immortality) or maybe even unethical. (because other versions of you will decide differently)
The odds are good that I’ve made a mistake somewhere. Probably, I’ve made the errors where I am thinking of my consciousness as something that is “sitting on” the quantum processes, riding them around and not getting off unless no Everett branch can support me (which is false, I am those same processes) or by not mapping onto the fact that those other Everett branches will be like me in many ways, because I am a complex system. (so if I decide to not buckle up and drive recklessly, it stands to reason that most of them will too)
Now, it is also possible that my intuitions are wrong: after all, I’ve never experienced meeting anyone with quantum immortality, but I don’t experience all Everett branches either. But it would seem odd for quantum immortality to be true and to never find myself down an Everett branch where someone has lived for 300 years, although I haven’t met every individual person either. If I did, I would conclude that consciousness did have some way of funnelling itself toward Everett branches where it was conserved. But I don’t conclude that QM or MW is wrong, I conclude that the bridge theory is wrong. One matches our observations, the other does not.
Thanks again for the excellent reply. It seems to me that the work of egan’s law is essentially the recommendation of this assumption once I have concluded something counterintuitive:
The odds are good that I’ve made a mistake somewhere.
That this recommendation triggers with claims (which I take it may nevertheless turn out true) like quantum immortality seems to be a function of the fact that quantum immortality theory does more explaining away and less endorsing of past observations and intuitions than a rival theory. Would you say that’s a fair description of Egan’s law then: a theory should be preferred if it endorses rather than explains away a greater proportion of past observations. If so (this seems very plausible to me), then egan’s law is a statement about the iterative nature of theoretical activity, rather than a statement about adding up to some absolute sphere of normality. After all, if we dragged a Cartesian physicist through time to learn some quantum physics, I doubt he would admit that it adds up to anything normal, all the way down to meta ethical concerns.
So is that egan’s law? That theoretical activity should always be an interation on past theory?
I actually disagree with you on the Cartesian physicist. QM would definitely seem counter-intuitive to him at first. But we really do have the advantage on the Cartesian physicist: we can explain why QM is right, how Newtonian and earlier physical theories just didn’t add up, and what they failed to explain. If this Cartesian physicist could put personal and political motives aside (not everyone can, but I don’t think that’s the substance of your claim) then he would, upon sufficient explanation, have to admit that QM was the correct theory.
Explain vs. explain away isn’t the issue here. As I’ve said, there are reasons why my beliefs on quantum immortality might be wrong and why there might be evidence even in the Everett branch in which I live that I am just not seeing. If you explain something, like why objects feel solid: great. If you explain something away, like why a stick appears bent when it is put in water: also great. The prohibition is against a theory dismissing observations.
Here’s a distinction that may help. It would seem odd for quantum immortality to happen but for no one in the past history of the Everett branch I travel down to have experienced it, or for this experience to have gone unnoted. But it seems downright implausible if a theory should lead to the conclusion that I do not exist at all. Or that I am an elephant. These would fly in the face of every reasonable observation. If an otherwise true theory stated that I didn’t exist, I would assume I made an incorrect inference, that being the most likely cause of the theory not adding up to normality. If the theory hinged on my non-existance, I would probably conclude the theory itself was wrong.
The most important part is noticing that you are confused: that something happened in that process that wasn’t right. It could be the theory is wrong, it could be a bad inference, but a good theory should explain your observations: past and present. It can either do this by explaining why the world is such that your observation matches reality or explaining why the world is such that your observation could occur even though it doesn’t match reality. The former being something like me seeing a stick on the ground (explained by optics, some knowledge of biology, and the fact that there is a stick on the ground) and the latter being something like me seeing that stick bend when put into water. (also explained by optics)
The prohibition is against a theory dismissing observations.
This seems to me to be a straw man though. No one would ever claim that it’s permissible for any theory to simply dismiss an observation. Just as no one would ever claim that since QM makes different predictions, physical events will now start happening differently.
Egan’s law can’t be that trivial, not if it’s going to do any argumentative work against the quantum immortalist or his ilk.
On the Cartesian, remember that the observations he would report would be observations of things like the flow of aether relative to a celestial body. He, and we, have no basic most observational language to fall back on and which is immune to theoretical revision. This is the whole thrust of my argument, and it means that you would have to go about talking the Cartesian out of his observations until you got to terms basic enough that you both endorse them. Like “no, what you observed was a light moving in such and such a way through the night sky”.
But we shouldn’t be mislead into thinking that these were the terms on which he made his observations in the first place, or that there is some level of description on which you and he are always going to agree. This doesn’t mean we can’t separate observations from explanations, only that there’s no prirncipled and fully general way to do so. There’s no fixed ‘normal’.
First, I have met a lot of your “no ones,” although they often dress up their dismissals in colorful language. It can be awfully tempting to dismiss “just this one” observation that can destroy an otherwise neat-looking theory, especially when you are invested in it.
Second, there is a difference between saying it does no argumentative work, and that it doesn’t do as much as you’d like. The former is false. The latter is a personal problem.
Lastly, to say that all observations are theory laden is not to say that you must handle every level of disagreement at once.
It seems you are making a fairly basic mistake here, assuming that because all observation is theory-laden, that people who have different paradigms cannot communicate. This is easily falsified. If I look up at the night sky and see something that my theories tell me is a “star” and the Cartesian looks up in the night sky and sees something that his theories tell him is a “crystal sphere” we can at least agree that we are both seeing something. We can also agree on the observational properties of the thing: what we observe about that thing. Its the empirical reality that provides a fixed ‘normal.’
And if we both have the same beliefs, but I am calling it a star while he is calling it a crystal sphere, then star=crystal sphere. If we do not both have the same beliefs, then one of us will either make incorrect statements about the object we are seeing which can be empirically falsified, or one of us will have a theory that makes a larger number of correct statements about the object than the other.
Minimally, we can point to the thing and say “Hey, let’s just agree we are talking about things like that. Okay?” Is there some theory there? Yes. Pointing, for instance, is theory-laden: it doesn’t describe anything to a rock. And there might be a being out there, somewhere, that has such a different theory of observation that pointing at something won’t work, yet it can still make empirical statements. This doesn’t mean that the emprically observed reality is not a fixed normal: it means that getting to that reality is difficult, but fortunately nature did a lot of that work in your DNA already.
You can also frame this as a reductio: if the empirical world is not a ‘fixed normal’ then which theories best describe reality should be dependent on just those same theories. But they aren’t: they are based in whatever observations we note match the predictions (past and present) of those theories. Does this include a theory about how “best describe reality”=”predictions match observations”? Yes. Again, we can follow the rabbit hole down as far as you like: we have very good reasons for thinking that predictions that match observations is equivalent to the best available description of reality. And no, I couldn’t describe this to a rock. But if you want a theory that can convince a rock… well, I would be interested if you found it, but I doubt you will.
It seems you are making a fairly basic mistake here, assuming that because all observation is theory-laden, that people who have different paradigms cannot communicate.
I’m not assuming this, or at least I don’t expect that I am, given that I don’t think it’s true. But the fact that we can communicate also doesn’t imply that there is a base observation language which we share and which provides a fixed normal. In other words, there are more than two options here. What would this language look like? It couldn’t include references to objective facts, since these can always be overturned by a theory. Mere experiences then? Aside from the serious problems sense data theories of epistemology face (and how unnecessary they are to preserve the empirical elements of science) there is simply the observation that no one who hasn’t been spending a lot of time with philosophers takes their normal world to consist in a collection of mere experiences.
We don’t require a base observation language: only the ability to point at things and agree that we are pointing at the same thing. The only thing that might qualify as a ‘base observation language’ is the neural impulses that send the sense data to my brain. Fortunate, then, that nature has taken care of that problem for us. It is the world, not our language about the world, that provides the fixed normal.
Further, the point of Egan’s law is that objective facts are not overturned by a theory. Rather, it is theories that are overturned by facts.
And of course your normal world doesn’t consist of just experiences: there are also your thoughts, dreams, emotions, motivations, theories, etc. Which is all well and good, and we can make observations about those, but we don’t have to. (We do, quite often, especially in cognitive psychology and neuroscience, but that’s a tangent) But experiences are how we determine what is true about the world, because that’s what works.
The only thing that might qualify as a ‘base observation language’ is the neural impulses that send the sense data to my brain. Fortunate, then, that nature has taken care of that problem for us. It is the world, not our language about the world, that provides the fixed normal.
I think this is something like the naturalistic fallacy in ethics: no physical or biological process can be said to have epistemic or justificatory value just because it is the kind of process that it is. This isn’t to say that such processes dont underlie my knowledge of the world in some sense, of course. The point is just that I can take a certain experience Of a blue object, say, as evidence for the existence of a blue object only because I have a bunch of prior knowledge about the relationship between those kinds of experiences and their correlation to the presence of blue objects in my visual field. Nothing about the firings of such and such a neural network is such as to be self-justifying or foundational. That would simply be a category mistake, like thinking that because my biology has produced in me certain inclinations toward my fellows, we can straight away take those inclinations to be a morality. Again, this doesn’t undermine the crucial importance of biology in our morality, just a certain way of concieving of that importance.
I think we’re miscommunicating on the ‘facts’ bit. What I mean is that if anything with extensional force, like ‘the apple is green’ can fall into the normal, then no theory should have to live up to it. The apple might really be blue. In fact, we might be convinced (haven’t we already?) that the physical objects of common sense, existing in space and enduring through time while bearing and changing properties like color are simply unreal. Science has superseded and contradicted common sense here, however much it might later explain the details of why we have the common sense picture that we do.
I’ll sum up my point by borrowing from someone else: ‘Empirical knowledge, like it’s sophisticated extension, science, is rational, not because it has a foundation but because it is a self-correcting enterprise which can put ANY claim in jeopardy, though not all at once.’
I want to tap out here, not because I think we’ve hit a dead end, but because I feel I’ve exhausted my resources. I’ve learned a lot from your replies, and I’ll happily read anything else you have to say on the matter. Thanks again.
Again, you have to remember that your ‘observation of a bent stick’ does not match all of the observations we have for bent sticks. If you put your fingers in the water and felt the stick bend, you would conclude that water bends sticks.
I don’t speak for EY, but I will try to answer:
First, in that particular quote, I hold that to be a promisary note (one that you might not feel he delivered on) that once you are done reading, it shouldn’t conflict with your normal intuitions. That said, I will try to answer your more specific worry.
QM’s straightforward reading endorses a many-world thesis, or something much like it. One can attempt to reject MW because we do not experience this “splitting,” or because it breaks down their notions of personal identity, or because they are unclear how it should alter their planning.
Saying that ‘It all adds up to normality’ here doesn’t mean that your intuitions about, say, personal identity can’t or shouldn’t change on the basis of what you learn about QM or MW. What it means is that if you suddenly conclude something like ”… so we don’t exist” either you made an error somewhere or the theory is wrong.
Let me try to make this more concrete: Say that I decide that because of QM and MW, that buckling my seatbelt and driving safely is either useless (quantum immortality) or maybe even unethical. (because other versions of you will decide differently)
The odds are good that I’ve made a mistake somewhere. Probably, I’ve made the errors where I am thinking of my consciousness as something that is “sitting on” the quantum processes, riding them around and not getting off unless no Everett branch can support me (which is false, I am those same processes) or by not mapping onto the fact that those other Everett branches will be like me in many ways, because I am a complex system. (so if I decide to not buckle up and drive recklessly, it stands to reason that most of them will too)
Now, it is also possible that my intuitions are wrong: after all, I’ve never experienced meeting anyone with quantum immortality, but I don’t experience all Everett branches either. But it would seem odd for quantum immortality to be true and to never find myself down an Everett branch where someone has lived for 300 years, although I haven’t met every individual person either. If I did, I would conclude that consciousness did have some way of funnelling itself toward Everett branches where it was conserved. But I don’t conclude that QM or MW is wrong, I conclude that the bridge theory is wrong. One matches our observations, the other does not.
Thanks again for the excellent reply. It seems to me that the work of egan’s law is essentially the recommendation of this assumption once I have concluded something counterintuitive:
That this recommendation triggers with claims (which I take it may nevertheless turn out true) like quantum immortality seems to be a function of the fact that quantum immortality theory does more explaining away and less endorsing of past observations and intuitions than a rival theory. Would you say that’s a fair description of Egan’s law then: a theory should be preferred if it endorses rather than explains away a greater proportion of past observations. If so (this seems very plausible to me), then egan’s law is a statement about the iterative nature of theoretical activity, rather than a statement about adding up to some absolute sphere of normality. After all, if we dragged a Cartesian physicist through time to learn some quantum physics, I doubt he would admit that it adds up to anything normal, all the way down to meta ethical concerns.
So is that egan’s law? That theoretical activity should always be an interation on past theory?
I actually disagree with you on the Cartesian physicist. QM would definitely seem counter-intuitive to him at first. But we really do have the advantage on the Cartesian physicist: we can explain why QM is right, how Newtonian and earlier physical theories just didn’t add up, and what they failed to explain. If this Cartesian physicist could put personal and political motives aside (not everyone can, but I don’t think that’s the substance of your claim) then he would, upon sufficient explanation, have to admit that QM was the correct theory.
Explain vs. explain away isn’t the issue here. As I’ve said, there are reasons why my beliefs on quantum immortality might be wrong and why there might be evidence even in the Everett branch in which I live that I am just not seeing. If you explain something, like why objects feel solid: great. If you explain something away, like why a stick appears bent when it is put in water: also great. The prohibition is against a theory dismissing observations.
Here’s a distinction that may help. It would seem odd for quantum immortality to happen but for no one in the past history of the Everett branch I travel down to have experienced it, or for this experience to have gone unnoted. But it seems downright implausible if a theory should lead to the conclusion that I do not exist at all. Or that I am an elephant. These would fly in the face of every reasonable observation. If an otherwise true theory stated that I didn’t exist, I would assume I made an incorrect inference, that being the most likely cause of the theory not adding up to normality. If the theory hinged on my non-existance, I would probably conclude the theory itself was wrong.
The most important part is noticing that you are confused: that something happened in that process that wasn’t right. It could be the theory is wrong, it could be a bad inference, but a good theory should explain your observations: past and present. It can either do this by explaining why the world is such that your observation matches reality or explaining why the world is such that your observation could occur even though it doesn’t match reality. The former being something like me seeing a stick on the ground (explained by optics, some knowledge of biology, and the fact that there is a stick on the ground) and the latter being something like me seeing that stick bend when put into water. (also explained by optics)
This seems to me to be a straw man though. No one would ever claim that it’s permissible for any theory to simply dismiss an observation. Just as no one would ever claim that since QM makes different predictions, physical events will now start happening differently.
Egan’s law can’t be that trivial, not if it’s going to do any argumentative work against the quantum immortalist or his ilk.
On the Cartesian, remember that the observations he would report would be observations of things like the flow of aether relative to a celestial body. He, and we, have no basic most observational language to fall back on and which is immune to theoretical revision. This is the whole thrust of my argument, and it means that you would have to go about talking the Cartesian out of his observations until you got to terms basic enough that you both endorse them. Like “no, what you observed was a light moving in such and such a way through the night sky”.
But we shouldn’t be mislead into thinking that these were the terms on which he made his observations in the first place, or that there is some level of description on which you and he are always going to agree. This doesn’t mean we can’t separate observations from explanations, only that there’s no prirncipled and fully general way to do so. There’s no fixed ‘normal’.
First, I have met a lot of your “no ones,” although they often dress up their dismissals in colorful language. It can be awfully tempting to dismiss “just this one” observation that can destroy an otherwise neat-looking theory, especially when you are invested in it.
Second, there is a difference between saying it does no argumentative work, and that it doesn’t do as much as you’d like. The former is false. The latter is a personal problem.
Lastly, to say that all observations are theory laden is not to say that you must handle every level of disagreement at once.
It seems you are making a fairly basic mistake here, assuming that because all observation is theory-laden, that people who have different paradigms cannot communicate. This is easily falsified. If I look up at the night sky and see something that my theories tell me is a “star” and the Cartesian looks up in the night sky and sees something that his theories tell him is a “crystal sphere” we can at least agree that we are both seeing something. We can also agree on the observational properties of the thing: what we observe about that thing. Its the empirical reality that provides a fixed ‘normal.’
And if we both have the same beliefs, but I am calling it a star while he is calling it a crystal sphere, then star=crystal sphere. If we do not both have the same beliefs, then one of us will either make incorrect statements about the object we are seeing which can be empirically falsified, or one of us will have a theory that makes a larger number of correct statements about the object than the other.
Minimally, we can point to the thing and say “Hey, let’s just agree we are talking about things like that. Okay?” Is there some theory there? Yes. Pointing, for instance, is theory-laden: it doesn’t describe anything to a rock. And there might be a being out there, somewhere, that has such a different theory of observation that pointing at something won’t work, yet it can still make empirical statements. This doesn’t mean that the emprically observed reality is not a fixed normal: it means that getting to that reality is difficult, but fortunately nature did a lot of that work in your DNA already.
You can also frame this as a reductio: if the empirical world is not a ‘fixed normal’ then which theories best describe reality should be dependent on just those same theories. But they aren’t: they are based in whatever observations we note match the predictions (past and present) of those theories. Does this include a theory about how “best describe reality”=”predictions match observations”? Yes. Again, we can follow the rabbit hole down as far as you like: we have very good reasons for thinking that predictions that match observations is equivalent to the best available description of reality. And no, I couldn’t describe this to a rock. But if you want a theory that can convince a rock… well, I would be interested if you found it, but I doubt you will.
I’m not assuming this, or at least I don’t expect that I am, given that I don’t think it’s true. But the fact that we can communicate also doesn’t imply that there is a base observation language which we share and which provides a fixed normal. In other words, there are more than two options here. What would this language look like? It couldn’t include references to objective facts, since these can always be overturned by a theory. Mere experiences then? Aside from the serious problems sense data theories of epistemology face (and how unnecessary they are to preserve the empirical elements of science) there is simply the observation that no one who hasn’t been spending a lot of time with philosophers takes their normal world to consist in a collection of mere experiences.
We don’t require a base observation language: only the ability to point at things and agree that we are pointing at the same thing. The only thing that might qualify as a ‘base observation language’ is the neural impulses that send the sense data to my brain. Fortunate, then, that nature has taken care of that problem for us. It is the world, not our language about the world, that provides the fixed normal.
Further, the point of Egan’s law is that objective facts are not overturned by a theory. Rather, it is theories that are overturned by facts.
And of course your normal world doesn’t consist of just experiences: there are also your thoughts, dreams, emotions, motivations, theories, etc. Which is all well and good, and we can make observations about those, but we don’t have to. (We do, quite often, especially in cognitive psychology and neuroscience, but that’s a tangent) But experiences are how we determine what is true about the world, because that’s what works.
I think this is something like the naturalistic fallacy in ethics: no physical or biological process can be said to have epistemic or justificatory value just because it is the kind of process that it is. This isn’t to say that such processes dont underlie my knowledge of the world in some sense, of course. The point is just that I can take a certain experience Of a blue object, say, as evidence for the existence of a blue object only because I have a bunch of prior knowledge about the relationship between those kinds of experiences and their correlation to the presence of blue objects in my visual field. Nothing about the firings of such and such a neural network is such as to be self-justifying or foundational. That would simply be a category mistake, like thinking that because my biology has produced in me certain inclinations toward my fellows, we can straight away take those inclinations to be a morality. Again, this doesn’t undermine the crucial importance of biology in our morality, just a certain way of concieving of that importance.
I think we’re miscommunicating on the ‘facts’ bit. What I mean is that if anything with extensional force, like ‘the apple is green’ can fall into the normal, then no theory should have to live up to it. The apple might really be blue. In fact, we might be convinced (haven’t we already?) that the physical objects of common sense, existing in space and enduring through time while bearing and changing properties like color are simply unreal. Science has superseded and contradicted common sense here, however much it might later explain the details of why we have the common sense picture that we do.
I’ll sum up my point by borrowing from someone else: ‘Empirical knowledge, like it’s sophisticated extension, science, is rational, not because it has a foundation but because it is a self-correcting enterprise which can put ANY claim in jeopardy, though not all at once.’
I want to tap out here, not because I think we’ve hit a dead end, but because I feel I’ve exhausted my resources. I’ve learned a lot from your replies, and I’ll happily read anything else you have to say on the matter. Thanks again.