Book Review: The Reputation Society. Part I
The Reputation Society (MIT Press, 2012), edited by Hassan Masum and Mark Tovey, is an anthology on the possibilities of using online rating and reputation systems to systematically disseminate information about virtually everything—people, goods and services, ideas, etc., etc. Even though the use of online rating systems is an overarching theme, the book is, however, quite heterogeneous (like many anthologies). I have therefore chosen to structure the material in a somewhat different way. This post consists of a short introduction to the book, while in the next, far longer post, I list a number of concepts and distinctions commented on by the authors (either explicitly or implicitly) and briefly summarize their take on them.
My hope is that this Wiki-style approach maximizes the amount of information per line of text. Also, though these concepts and distinctions are arguably the most useful stuff in the book, they are unfortunately not gathered in any one place in the book. Hence I think that my list should be of use for those that go on to read the book, or parts of it. I also hope that this list of entries could be a start to a series of Less Wrong Wiki entries on reputation systems. Moreover, it could be a good point of departure for general discussions on rating and reputation systems. I would be happy to receive feedback on this choice of presentation form (as well as on the content, of course).
A chapter-by-chapter review (more of a guide to what chapters to read, really) can be found on my blog. (This review is already too long which is why I put the chapter-by-chapter overview there rather than here at Less Wrong.) Monique Sadarangani has also written a review (which focuses on various legal aspects of online rating systems). Another associated text you might consider reading is Masum’s and Yi-Cheng Zhang’s “Manifesto for the Reputation Society” (2004).
Introduction
People have of course always relied on others’ recommendations on a massive scale. We often don’t have time to figure out who is reliable and who is not, what goods are worth buying and what are not, which university education is valued by employers and which is not, etc. Instead we look to the testimonies and recommendations of others.
As pointed out by several of the authors, these recommendations have, however, often been given in a quite unsystematic fashion. In small societies, this lack of systematicity and structure was, though, to some extent outweighed by the wealth of information you would obtain about any individual person or item. Everybody knew everybody, which meant that a crook would sooner or later typically be identified as such, even though information about people’s trustworthiness was not being spread in an organized, rational fashion.
However, when people moved into cities, it became easier for dishonest people to hide in the crowds. One-off encounters with strangers became much more common, and with them the incentives to cheat increased: these strangers could typically not identify you, which meant that your reputation was not damaged by dishonorable behavior (see chs. 4, 6).
The inhabitants of cities, particularly those working in professions such as trade, tried to counter these problems by forming associations which guaranteed that their members conducted themselves properly (or else they would be thrown out). As the complexity of society has increased, so has the number and efficiency of these recommendation and reputation systems (italicized terms appear as entries in the next post). Today there are countless organizations that keep track of the creditworthiness of individuals (e.g., FICO), companies and countries (e.g., Standard & Poor and Moody), the quality of education (e.g., The Guardian’s University League Table, which provides an influential annual university ranking in the UK), the quality of restaurants (Guide Michelin), etc.
As virtually all of the authors argue, the Internet offers, however, spectacular opportunities for constructing rating systems that are more reliable and vastly much more pervasive than anything yet seen. The editors sum up this optimism in their introduction (Location 182, 2nd page of introduction):
In today’s world, reliable advice from others’ experience is often unavailable, whether for buying products, choosing a service, or judging a policy. One promising solution is to bring to reputation a similar kind of systematization as currencies, laws, and accounting brought to primitive barter economies. Properly designed reputation systems have the potential to reshape society for the better by shining the light of accountability into dark places, through the mediated judgments of billions of people worldwide, to create what we call the Reputation Society.
There are of course already a great number of Internet rating systems, including those used by Google, Facebook (the like system), Amazon, eBay, Slashdot, Yelp, Netflix, Reddit, and, not to forget, Less Wrong. Many of these systems are discussed in the book (not Less Wrong, though). In particular, the authors try to assess what we can learn from the successes and failures of these rating sites.
There is a general (though seldom explicitly stated) sentiment in the book that the existing rating systems do not nearly exhaust the opportunities that the Internet provides us with. I certainly share this sentiment. As pointed out in ch. 5 (see the entry Underutilization of reputational information), people make a great number of “private judgments” in their heads which it would be very useful for others to learn about, but which they do not share. If they could be persuaded to share them to a greater extent, the social gains would be huge. If consumers got more reliable information about the quality of different goods and services (via consumer rating systems), the providers of those items would be forced to increase the quality of their products. In some areas, this is already happening, but other areas are lagging. The potential gains stretch far beyond goods and services, though: public debates would be conducted more rationally if rating systems penalized bullshitters (ch. 15), government would be better run if its actions and policies were rated in a rational way (ch. 13), science could improve if peers rated others’ work in a more rational way than they do at present (chs. 10-12). You would even imagine people rating your life plans, your behavior, and other stuff that is primarily interesting to yourself. Only imagination puts a limit to the potential uses of rating systems.
Even though there is some research on rating systems—on which Chrysantos (Chris) Dellarocas, the author of the first chapter, is an expert—most rating systems seem to be created in a quite unsystematic, trial-and-error fashion. Instead we should draw from the full range of the social sciences – e.g., from psychology, sociology, economics, law, history, anthropology and political sciences – when constructing such systems. I am convinced that we could benefit greatly as a society if we spent more time and resources on the construction of efficient rating systems. I also think that the Less Wrong community, with its combination of an intellectually curious and rational attitude and strong programming skills, potentially has a lot to contribute here.
At the same time, one shouldn’t get over-optimistic. There are lots of hurdles to pass. I certainly do not share the wild optimism of Craig Newmark, the founder of Craigslist, who writes as follows in the foreword (Location 70, 1st page of Foreword):
By the end of this decade, power and influence will have shifted largely to those people with the best reputations and trust networks and away from people with money and nominal power. That is, peer networks will confer legitimacy on people emerging from the grassroots.
These bold words remind me of some similarly bold predictions of how prediction markets, Wikis, and other forms of collective enterprises in the spirit of the Wisdom of the crowd will transform society and especially human knowledge, made in Cass Sunstein’s Infotopia (2006). So far, Sunstein’s predictions haven’t been borne out and the odds don’t look too good for Newmark, either. I do agree with Newmark that there is a huge potential in rating systems, but realizing that potential is not going to happen by itself. It will take lots of testing, lots of ingenuity, lots of hard work, and certainly a considerably greater amount of time than Newmark believes, to do that.
- Does the Internet lead to good ideas spreading quicker? by 28 Oct 2015 22:30 UTC; 14 points) (
- Three methods of attaining change by 16 Aug 2014 15:38 UTC; 12 points) (
- Could auto-generated troll scores reduce Twitter and Facebook harassments? by 30 Apr 2015 14:05 UTC; 7 points) (
- Social effects of algorithms that accurately identify human behaviour and traits by 14 May 2016 10:48 UTC; 6 points) (
Indeed, I doubt that “those people with the best reputations and trust networks” and “people with money and nominal power” are especially distinct groups. And insofar as peer networks do successfully “confer legitimacy on people emerging from the grassroots”, I expect them to make the two groups more similar, not less. (Reputation, or at least fame, just isn’t very egalitarian.)
Interesting. Thanks for the link also. I think you’re right that under an efficient reputational system, people with good reputation would be rich and powerful. Indeed, that notion is implied in the title (“The Reputation Society”) and is expressed in some of the chapters (especially the two last ones).
If your reputation mirrored your merits, this would also make society more meritocratic. If so, that would be the continuation of a long historical process. In the feudal age, you could be rich and powerful just because of your lineage. Thanks to the market economy, your income correlates to a far higher degree with your merits today. Efficient reputational systems would improve the functioning of the market economy and make this correlation even stronger.
Could you please elaborate this further? I understand that people are unequal in money, and unequal in prestige, but I’m not sure whether/why you think these two would be correlated. Especially if prestige could also have negative values (as opposed to “negative publicity is also publicity” fame, which is much easier to buy for money), which could happen to rich people who abuse their power.
Do you mean that rich people could generate trust, or rather that trustworthy people could generate money? The former seems bad to me, the latter seems good, but the end result of both would be greater correlation between money and trust.
You can use money to buy prestige (if you want to and not stupid in going about it) and you can use prestige to get money (if you want to and not stupid in going about it).
See The Forms of Capital
Not sure if this would be his argument, but time can be spent acquiring reputation (e.g. politicians knocking on doors, for a straightforward if inefficient example) or money, and having more money reduces your need to spend time acquiring more, thus freeing up time to acquire reputation.
Additionally, money makes it much easier to acquire fame, and fame would certainly magnify any reputation losses/gains.
Sure. Lumifer’s given a concise summary already, so I’ll zoom in a bit with some specific examples.
If I am (for example) a YouTube poster with no money but a good reputation — i.e. if lots of people follow my account and watch my videos — I can make money by selling merchandise or convincing people to donate, or through YouTube’s official programme for monetizing videos through advertising and paid subscriptions. In the long run I could even use it as a launchpad for getting a TV series or a film.
Alternatively, if I’m rich but don’t have a good reputation, I can pay a PR company to come up with articles that say nice things about me and have them circulated on popular websites, pay an SEO company to help bury embarrassing Google results and promote more PR-friendly stuff, or pay to run a high-quality online magazine or newspaper so I can benefit from the halo effect.
Of course, wealth and trust/prestige don’t have to be positively correlated just because of the above. (Wealth can be used to destroy a reputation, too.) But in practice the two seem positively correlated to me, and mechanisms like those I’ve mentioned are very likely one reason why.
Writing feedback: You don’t need the word “however” in the second sentence; it’s ungrammatical, and a contrast is already implied by the phrase “even though”.
(that said, this is an interesting topic and I appreciate that you’re doing this review :-) )