Why comparative advantage does not help horses

This post discusses what statements about comparative advantage say and what they do not say, and why comparative advantage does not save horses from getting sent to glue factories. It is only marginally about AI.

Eliezer Yudkowsky, in “The Sun is big, but superintelligences will not spare Earth a little sunlight”, explains Ricardo’s Law of Comparative Advantage and then writes:

Ricardo’s Law doesn’t say, “Horses won’t get sent to glue factories after cars roll out.”

Ricardo’s Law doesn’t say (alas!) that—when Europe encounters a new continent—Europe can become selfishly wealthier by peacefully trading with the Native Americans, and leaving them their land.

Their labor wasn’t necessarily more profitable than the land they lived on.

Comparative Advantage doesn’t imply that Earth can produce more with $77 of sunlight, than a superintelligence can produce with $77 of sunlight, in goods and services valued by superintelligences. It would actually be rather odd if this were the case!

These (negative) statements are true, but they may also create confusion. Why? Because they suggest something unclear or wrong about what Ricardo’s insight does and does not apply to—i.e., what comparative advantage is about.

Eliezer presents a standard example of comparative advantage, two countries trading, and he says that “Ricardo’s Law of Comparative Advantage, … shows that even if the country of Freedonia is more productive in every way than the country of Sylvania, both countries still benefit from trading with each other.” But what does this require?

It is useful to consider Ricardo’s example. It starts from a situation in which, in “the absence of trade, England requires 220 hours of work to both produce and consume one unit each of cloth and wine while Portugal requires 170 hours of work to produce and consume the same quantities”. Given their production technologies, their natural endowments, or economies of scale (depending on the aspect of reality you are focusing on, or on the trade model you are employing), the countries together can produce more if they specialize. Or, as Wikipedia puts it after presenting a “typical modern interpretation of the classical Ricardian model”: “by trading and specializing in a good for which it has a comparative advantage, each country can expand its consumption possibilities. Consumers can choose from bundles of wine and cloth that they could not have produced themselves in closed economies.

So Ricardo’s model, first of all, tells us that by specializing, the countries can produce more.

The distribution of this surplus has to (weakly) benefit both countries. If wine is too expensive for the country that specializes in producing cloth, then it does not specialize in producing cloth. If there are two people, two countries, or two machines that are worse off by trading, then they don’t trade.

Worse off compared to what? Worse off than if they were on their own. For this comparison to make sense, the trading partners must be able to decide to be left alone. The trading partners must have ownership over themselves.

If in the seminal economic model of Ricardo’s evil doppelgänger in the Mirror Universe, the dictator of England simply conquered Portugal (and thereby got rid of trade barriers) and forced everybody there to produce wine, cloth or whatever, then the dictator should still choose an efficient labor allocation between the two countries, but whether this is good for Portugal of bad depends on the dictator’s preferences. The outside option in the original Ricardo model is self-sufficiency; the outside option in the economic model of Mirror-Universe Ricardo is death.

Noting that specialization and self-ownership are central to Ricardo’s model, let us reconsider the claims quoted in the beginning:

“Horses won’t get sent to glue factories after cars roll out.”

This may be true; however, the reason is not a failure of comparative advantage, but the fact that the theory of comparative advantage does not apply. Horses never chose to “trade” with their owners. They could not opt out.

“Ricardo’s Law doesn’t say (alas!) that—when Europe encounters a new continent—Europe can become selfishly wealthier by peacefully trading with the Native Americans, and leaving them their land.

Their labor wasn’t necessarily more profitable than the land they lived on.”

Ricardo’s model does say that “Europe can become selfishly wealthier by peacefully trading with the Native Americans, and leaving them their land.” However, it may be the case that Europeans can become even wealthier by taking the land. Relative strengths and their assessments change over time, and times in which group A respects the ownership rights of group B may not last forever.

Moreover, maybe there is no real necessity to choose between taking the labor and taking the land; sometimes a conqueror takes both. However, if a conqueror cannot just command the labor of the conquered, then it is possible that the people who are conquered die.

“Comparative Advantage doesn’t imply that Earth can produce more with $77 of sunlight, than a superintelligence can produce with $77 of sunlight, in goods and services valued by superintelligences. It would actually be rather odd if this were the case!”

Applying the reasoning of the comparative-advantage model to this situation may be misleading. The assumed superintelligence can take what it wants to take, and if people could “produce more with $77 of sunlight, than a superintelligence can produce with $77 of sunlight”, then it could probably force people to produce it.