It’s hard to distinguish symbiotic wars from dead antimemes.
I think it is possible to make good use of past antimemes in a way that draws attention to their antimemetic character.
“Tell me,” Wittgenstein’s asked a friend, “why do people always say, it was natural for man to assume that the sun went round the earth rather than that the earth was rotating?” His friend replied, “Well, obviously because it just looks as though the Sun is going round the Earth.” Wittgenstein replied, “Well, what would it have looked like if it had looked as though the Earth was rotating?”
The straussian reading of ‘people who engage in philosophy’
Memeplexes engaged in blackmail by causing their adherents to suffer if you try to prevent the conditions favorable to the meme indoctrinating more people. If that’s too abstract imagine a cancer that causes pain if you don’t eat sugar.
Suffering itself is an anti meme and one ea (mostly, so far) failed to not do substitution effect on.
I didn’t know what “straussian” means so I looked it up.
The “Straussian” approach to the history of political philosophy is articulated primarily in the writings of Leo Strauss. Strauss wrote extremely careful, detailed studies of canonical philosophical works along with essays explaining his approach. The most controversial claim Strauss made was that philosophers in the past did not always present their thoughts openly and explicitly. They used an “art of writing” to entice potential philosophers to begin a life of inquiry by following the hints the authors gave about their true thoughts and questions. The overriding purpose of Strauss’s own studies was to prove that philosophy in its original Socratic form is still possible by showing the persistence of certain fundamental problems throughout the history of philosophy. The most pertinent of those problems, not merely to political philosophy but to human life as a whole, was the problem of justice. Strauss also insisted that “historicism” is based on a philosophical account of the character and limitations of human knowledge and that it can be refuted, therefore, only on the basis of a philosophical argument. ― The Straussian Approach by Catherine Zuckert in The Oxford Handbook of the History of Political Philosophy
But I can’t tell exactly what ‘people who engage in philosophy’ means and why it’s in quotes. It sounds like the title of an essay but a web search doesn’t find anything.
Do you feel comfortable giving an example of such a memeplex?
Suffering is indeed an antimeme—and a broad-ranging one too. This is a new addition to my collection. Thanks.
I didn’t know what the substitution effect is either so here’s a definition.
The substitution effect is the decrease in sales for a product that can be attributed to consumers switching to cheaper alternatives when its price rises. ― Source
Whoops different substitution effect. The tendency to replace a difficult question with an easier one without noticing that we did so. Related to bike shedding and aether variables.
I’m not sure that rule works, when discussing patterns and relative applicability of models (which are integral to many discussions about rationality). How many and how fully the given examples work to reify a theory is usually in scope for the debate.
If the examples are idiosyncratic to some audiences, or controversial in applicability, then perhaps the theory is also useful only for those subsets.
You can come up with a theory, grounded on principles that seem reasonable, rather than focusing on gathering evidence. In the end, the theory has to explain not “the facts” but “the observations”.
Pervasive error is any systematic and significant distortion of thought that impacts the whole discourse of a civilization.
...
We can only build a useful theory of pervasive error by working carefully forward from axiomatic principles, not backward from observed reality—thinking logically, not scientifically.
I know this is weird. Let’s start by justifying this unconventional methodology.
So let’s avoid the factual question of whether modern pervasive error exists. Instead we’ll ask a theoretical question: if pervasive error did exist, what would it look like? How would it work? What would we expect its effects to be?
A well-formed answer is a constructive proof. We reason forward—from ultimate cause, to proximate cause, to phenomenon. The way to explain error is to design error.
Once such a design for error is clearly presented, anyone can compare it to the reality they think they see around them. If they see a match, they have an explanation.
If not—maybe there is some other explanation. Or maybe there is no error at all. In the end, everyone makes this call alone. Your horse is a horse. Eventually he will get thirsty.
I appreciate this article very much. I read the whole thing and was disappointed when I realized Curtis Yarvin hadn’t finished the series yet. It already has many great insights and illuminating points. I’ll be digesting the implications for a while.
Diversity of approaches is important in this game. My favorite things about it is how Yarvin attacks a closely-related problem from a different perspective. In particular:
He focuses on the political economy. (I deliberately de-emphasize politics when choosing where to focus.)
He debugs things from first principles. “It is always better to debug forward.” (I prefer to debug backwards.)
I agree with almost everything he says. I disagree with his claim that it is “always” better to debug forward. Debugging forward is better when you have a small dataset, as is the case with the historic sweep of broad political ideologies (the subject of Yavin’s writing). I think when you’re dealing with smaller problems, like niche technical decisions, there’s a greater diversity of data and therefore a greater opportunity to figure things out inductively.
Debugging forward is better when you have a small dataset,
I’d say the difference is about something different (trust/belief/etc.). Maybe it’s hard to find people who, upon seeing a proof whose conclusion they disagree with, actually examine it for the flaw. (Or people who want proofs.) Experimentation may enable finding ways to improve, working through everything logically may enable finding the optimal/closed form solution, Fermi estimates enable finding the order of magnitude of an effect (though this isn’t distinct from experimentation).
I think it is possible to make good use of past antimemes in a way that draws attention to their antimemetic character.
Wonder what antimemes are an integral part of the LW egregore.
The straussian reading of ‘people who engage in philosophy’
Memeplexes engaged in blackmail by causing their adherents to suffer if you try to prevent the conditions favorable to the meme indoctrinating more people. If that’s too abstract imagine a cancer that causes pain if you don’t eat sugar.
Suffering itself is an anti meme and one ea (mostly, so far) failed to not do substitution effect on.
I didn’t know what “straussian” means so I looked it up.
But I can’t tell exactly what ‘people who engage in philosophy’ means and why it’s in quotes. It sounds like the title of an essay but a web search doesn’t find anything.
Do you feel comfortable giving an example of such a memeplex?
Suffering is indeed an antimeme—and a broad-ranging one too. This is a new addition to my collection. Thanks.
I didn’t know what the substitution effect is either so here’s a definition.
Whoops different substitution effect. The tendency to replace a difficult question with an easier one without noticing that we did so. Related to bike shedding and aether variables.
the correct name is attribution substitution.
“philosophers claim they are seeking truth but they are really seeking peace”
I’m not sure that rule works, when discussing patterns and relative applicability of models (which are integral to many discussions about rationality). How many and how fully the given examples work to reify a theory is usually in scope for the debate.
If the examples are idiosyncratic to some audiences, or controversial in applicability, then perhaps the theory is also useful only for those subsets.
You can come up with a theory, grounded on principles that seem reasonable, rather than focusing on gathering evidence. In the end, the theory has to explain not “the facts” but “the observations”.
That’s a good idea. I hadn’t thought about it like that.
Then you might appreciate (at least the first part) of this article: https://americanmind.org/essays/the-clear-pill-part-2-of-5-a-theory-of-pervasive-error/
I appreciate this article very much. I read the whole thing and was disappointed when I realized Curtis Yarvin hadn’t finished the series yet. It already has many great insights and illuminating points. I’ll be digesting the implications for a while.
Diversity of approaches is important in this game. My favorite things about it is how Yarvin attacks a closely-related problem from a different perspective. In particular:
He focuses on the political economy. (I deliberately de-emphasize politics when choosing where to focus.)
He debugs things from first principles. “It is always better to debug forward.” (I prefer to debug backwards.)
I agree with almost everything he says. I disagree with his claim that it is “always” better to debug forward. Debugging forward is better when you have a small dataset, as is the case with the historic sweep of broad political ideologies (the subject of Yavin’s writing). I think when you’re dealing with smaller problems, like niche technical decisions, there’s a greater diversity of data and therefore a greater opportunity to figure things out inductively.
I’d say the difference is about something different (trust/belief/etc.). Maybe it’s hard to find people who, upon seeing a proof whose conclusion they disagree with, actually examine it for the flaw. (Or people who want proofs.) Experimentation may enable finding ways to improve, working through everything logically may enable finding the optimal/closed form solution, Fermi estimates enable finding the order of magnitude of an effect (though this isn’t distinct from experimentation).