And, presumably, assign one district each to LA and NY? I bet you can guess the answer.
The trouble with these spatial examples is that everyone has all these pesky intuitions lying around. “Space is continuous, of course!” we think, and “cities are made of parts!” But the formal statement of the problem, if the principle of indifference is to be useful, must generally be quite low-information—if the symmetry between the cities is thoroughly broken by us having tons of knowledge about the cities, the example is false as stated.
In order to get in the low-information mindset, it helps to replace meaningful (to us) labels with meaningless ones. In the first “formalization,” all we know is that Julia Roberts could be in one of 3 named cities. Avoiding labels, all we know is that agent 1 could have mutually exclusive and exhaustive properties A, B and C. As soon as the problem is stated this way it becomes clearer that you can’t just condense properties B and C together without changing the problem.
And, presumably, assign one district each to LA and NY?
I never said that?
But the formal statement of the problem, if the principle of indifference is to be useful, must generally be quite low-information -
Why does “the formal statement of the problem” matter? Reality doesn’t depend on how the problem is phrased.
You seem to be trying to find an answer that would satisfy a hypothetical teacher not the answer that you would use if you had something to protect.
In order to get in the low-information mindset, it helps to replace meaningful (to us) labels with meaningless ones. In the first “formalization,” all we know is that Julia Roberts could be in one of 3 named cities. Avoiding labels, all we know is that agent 1 could have mutually exclusive and exhaustive properties A, B and C. As soon as the problem is stated this way it becomes clearer that you can’t just condense properties B and C together without changing the problem.
Suppose I instead called the options A1, B1 and B2. Renaming the options shouldn’t change anything after all.
And, presumably, assign one district each to LA and NY? I bet you can guess the answer.
The trouble with these spatial examples is that everyone has all these pesky intuitions lying around. “Space is continuous, of course!” we think, and “cities are made of parts!” But the formal statement of the problem, if the principle of indifference is to be useful, must generally be quite low-information—if the symmetry between the cities is thoroughly broken by us having tons of knowledge about the cities, the example is false as stated.
In order to get in the low-information mindset, it helps to replace meaningful (to us) labels with meaningless ones. In the first “formalization,” all we know is that Julia Roberts could be in one of 3 named cities. Avoiding labels, all we know is that agent 1 could have mutually exclusive and exhaustive properties A, B and C. As soon as the problem is stated this way it becomes clearer that you can’t just condense properties B and C together without changing the problem.
I never said that?
Why does “the formal statement of the problem” matter? Reality doesn’t depend on how the problem is phrased.
You seem to be trying to find an answer that would satisfy a hypothetical teacher not the answer that you would use if you had something to protect.
Suppose I instead called the options A1, B1 and B2. Renaming the options shouldn’t change anything after all.