Epistemic status: I might be reinventing the wheel here
A common cause for rejection of total utilitarianism is that it implies the so-called Repugnant Conclusion, of which a lot has been written elsewhere. I will argue that while this implication is solid in theory, it does not apply in our current known universe. My view is similar to the one expressed here, but I try to give more details.
The Repugnant Conclusion IRL
The greatest relevance of the RC in practice arises in situations of scarce resources and Malthusian population traps¹: We compare population A, where there are few people with each one having plentiful resources, and population Z, which has grown from A until the average person lives in near-subsistence conditions.
Let’s formalize this a bit: suppose each person requires 1 unit of resources for living, so that the utility of a person living on 1 resources is exactly 0: a completely neutral life. Furthermore, suppose utility is linear w.r.t. resources: doubling resources means doubling utility and 10 resources correspond to 1 utility. If there are 100 resources in the world, population A might contain 10 people with 10 resources each and total utility 10; population Z might contain 99 people with 100⁄99 resources each and total utility also 10.
So in this model, we are indifferent between A and Z even as everyone in Z is barely subsisting, and this would be the Repugnant Conclusion². But this conclusion depends crucially on the relationship between resources and utility which we have assumed to be linear. What if our assumption is wrong? What is this relationship in the actual world? Note that this is an empirical question³.
It is well known that self-reported happiness varies logarithmically with income⁴, both between countries and for individuals within each country, so it seems reasonable to assume that the utility-resources relation is logarithmic: exponential increases in resources bring linear increases in utility.
Back to our model, assuming log utility, how do we now compare A and Z? If utility per person is ui=logri where ri are the resources available to that person, then total utility is U=Σlogri . Assuming equality in the population (see the Equality section), if Rare total resources and N is population size, each person has resources ri=R/N and so we have
U=ΣlogRN=Σ(logR−logN)=N(logR−logN)
We can plot total utility (vertical axis) as a function of N (horizontal axis) for R=100
Here we can see two extremes of cero utility: at N=0 where there are no persons and at N=100 where each person lives with 1 resources, at subsistence level. In the middle there is a sweet spot, and the maximum M lies at around 37 people⁵.
Now we can answer our question! Population A, where N=10 is better than population Z where N=99, but M is a superior alternative to both.
So I have shown that there is a population M greater and better than A where everyone is worse off, how is that different from the RC? Well, the difference is that this does not happen for every population, but only for those where average well being is relatively high. Furthermore, the average individual in M is far above subsistence.
Equality
In my model I assumed an equal distribution of resources over the population, mainly to simplify the calculations, but also because under the log relationship and if the population is held constant, total utilitarianism endorses equality. I will try to give an intuition for this and then a formal proof.
This graph represents individual utility (vertical axis) vs individual resources (horizontal axis). If there are two people, A and B, each having 2.5 and 7.5 resources respectively, we can reallocate resources so that both now are at point M, with 5 each. Note that the increase in utility for A is 3, while the decrease for B is a bit less than 2, so total utility increases by more than 1.
This happens no matter where in the graph are A and B due to the properties of the log function. As long as there is a difference in wealth you can increase total utility by redistributing resources equally.
For a formal proof, see ⁶.
Implications
The main conclusion I get from this is that although total utilitarianism is far from perfect, it might give good results in practice. The Repugnant Conclusion is not dead, however. We can certainly imagine some sentient aliens, AIs or animals whose utility function is such that greater, worse-average-utility populations end up being better. But in this case, should we really call it repugnant? Could our intuition be fine-tuned for thinking about humans, and thus not applicable to those hypothetical beings?
I don’t know to what extent have others explored the connection between total utilitarianism and equality, but I was surprised when I realized that the former could imply the latter. Of course, even if total utility is all that matters, it might not be possible to reshuffle it among individuals with complete liberty, which is the case in my model.
Footnotes
1: One might consider other ways of controlling individual utility in a population besides resources (e.g. mind design, torture...) but these seem less relevant to me.
2: Actually, in the original formulation Z is shown to be better than A, not just equally good.
3: As long as utility is well defined, that is. Here I will use self-reported happiness as a proxy for utility.
5: We can find the exact maximum for any R with a bit of calculus:
dUdN=logR−logN−loge=0
N=10logR−loge=Re−1
A nice property of this is that the ratio R/N that maximizes U is constant for al R(the exact constant e−1 obtained here is just due to the arbitrary choice of base 10 for the logarithms)
6: For a population of N individuals the distribution of R resources which maximizes total utility U=Σlogri is that where ri=R/N for all i. The proof goes by induction on N.
This is obvious in the case N=1. For the induction step, we can separate a population of N+1 into two sets of N and 1 individuals respectively so that total utility is U=Σi∈{1..N}logri+logrN+1. Suppose we allocate RN resources to the group of N, and R−RN to the last person. By hypothesis, each of the N people must receive RN/N resources to maximize their total utility so U=N(logRN−logN)+log(R−RN)
Now we have to decide how much should RN be.
dUdRN=NRNln10−1(R−RN)ln10=0
Solving for RN:
RN=RNN+1
Therefore, for each of the N first individuals ri=RN/N=R/(N+1) and for the last one rn+1=R−RN=R(1−NN+1)=R/(N+1)
Logarithms and Total Utilitarianism
Epistemic status: I might be reinventing the wheel here
A common cause for rejection of total utilitarianism is that it implies the so-called Repugnant Conclusion, of which a lot has been written elsewhere. I will argue that while this implication is solid in theory, it does not apply in our current known universe. My view is similar to the one expressed here, but I try to give more details.
The Repugnant Conclusion IRL
The greatest relevance of the RC in practice arises in situations of scarce resources and Malthusian population traps¹: We compare population A, where there are few people with each one having plentiful resources, and population Z, which has grown from A until the average person lives in near-subsistence conditions.
Let’s formalize this a bit: suppose each person requires 1 unit of resources for living, so that the utility of a person living on 1 resources is exactly 0: a completely neutral life. Furthermore, suppose utility is linear w.r.t. resources: doubling resources means doubling utility and 10 resources correspond to 1 utility. If there are 100 resources in the world, population A might contain 10 people with 10 resources each and total utility 10; population Z might contain 99 people with 100⁄99 resources each and total utility also 10.
So in this model, we are indifferent between A and Z even as everyone in Z is barely subsisting, and this would be the Repugnant Conclusion². But this conclusion depends crucially on the relationship between resources and utility which we have assumed to be linear. What if our assumption is wrong? What is this relationship in the actual world? Note that this is an empirical question³.
It is well known that self-reported happiness varies logarithmically with income⁴, both between countries and for individuals within each country, so it seems reasonable to assume that the utility-resources relation is logarithmic: exponential increases in resources bring linear increases in utility.
Back to our model, assuming log utility, how do we now compare A and Z? If utility per person is ui=logri where ri are the resources available to that person, then total utility is U=Σlogri . Assuming equality in the population (see the Equality section), if R are total resources and N is population size, each person has resources ri=R/N and so we have
We can plot total utility (vertical axis) as a function of N (horizontal axis) for R=100
Here we can see two extremes of cero utility: at N=0 where there are no persons and at N=100 where each person lives with 1 resources, at subsistence level. In the middle there is a sweet spot, and the maximum M lies at around 37 people⁵.
Now we can answer our question! Population A, where N=10 is better than population Z where N=99, but M is a superior alternative to both.
So I have shown that there is a population M greater and better than A where everyone is worse off, how is that different from the RC? Well, the difference is that this does not happen for every population, but only for those where average well being is relatively high. Furthermore, the average individual in M is far above subsistence.
Equality
In my model I assumed an equal distribution of resources over the population, mainly to simplify the calculations, but also because under the log relationship and if the population is held constant, total utilitarianism endorses equality. I will try to give an intuition for this and then a formal proof.
This graph represents individual utility (vertical axis) vs individual resources (horizontal axis). If there are two people, A and B, each having 2.5 and 7.5 resources respectively, we can reallocate resources so that both now are at point M, with 5 each. Note that the increase in utility for A is 3, while the decrease for B is a bit less than 2, so total utility increases by more than 1.
This happens no matter where in the graph are A and B due to the properties of the log function. As long as there is a difference in wealth you can increase total utility by redistributing resources equally.
For a formal proof, see ⁶.
Implications
The main conclusion I get from this is that although total utilitarianism is far from perfect, it might give good results in practice. The Repugnant Conclusion is not dead, however. We can certainly imagine some sentient aliens, AIs or animals whose utility function is such that greater, worse-average-utility populations end up being better. But in this case, should we really call it repugnant? Could our intuition be fine-tuned for thinking about humans, and thus not applicable to those hypothetical beings?
I don’t know to what extent have others explored the connection between total utilitarianism and equality, but I was surprised when I realized that the former could imply the latter. Of course, even if total utility is all that matters, it might not be possible to reshuffle it among individuals with complete liberty, which is the case in my model.
Footnotes
1: One might consider other ways of controlling individual utility in a population besides resources (e.g. mind design, torture...) but these seem less relevant to me.
2: Actually, in the original formulation Z is shown to be better than A, not just equally good.
3: As long as utility is well defined, that is. Here I will use self-reported happiness as a proxy for utility.
4: See the charts here
5: We can find the exact maximum for any R with a bit of calculus:
A nice property of this is that the ratio R/N that maximizes U is constant for al R(the exact constant e−1 obtained here is just due to the arbitrary choice of base 10 for the logarithms)
6: For a population of N individuals the distribution of R resources which maximizes total utility U=Σlogri is that where ri=R/N for all i. The proof goes by induction on N.
This is obvious in the case N=1. For the induction step, we can separate a population of N+1 into two sets of N and 1 individuals respectively so that total utility is U=Σi∈{1..N}logri+logrN+1. Suppose we allocate RN resources to the group of N, and R−RN to the last person. By hypothesis, each of the N people must receive RN/N resources to maximize their total utility so U=N(logRN−logN)+log(R−RN)
Now we have to decide how much should RN be.
Therefore, for each of the N first individuals ri=RN/N=R/(N+1) and for the last one rn+1=R−RN=R(1−NN+1)=R/(N+1)