I believe you’re being uncharitable. JS is a bit effervescent and waxes poetic in a few places, but doesn’t say anything obviously wrong.
I would have assumed (perhaps wrongly) that you’d know how to take the Lie derivative of a (1, 1)-tensor field, and there’s only a short Googling necessary to ascertain that complex structures are certain kinds of (1, 1)-tensor fields. The linked draft is pretty clear about what L_X(J) = 0 means, and that makes it clear what L_X(J) != 0 means—X doesn’t generate holomorphic flows.
In another comment, he shows how to construct a compatible (almost) complex structure J from a Riemannian structure g and a symplectic structure w. This is actually a special case of a theorem of Arnol’d, which states that fixing any two yields a compatible choice of the third. (I’ve always heard this called the “two out of three” theorem, but apparently some computer science thing has overtaken this name.) This shows that J is actually relevant to the dynamics of the underlying system—just as relevant as the symplectic structure is.
From that, it’s not too much of a stretch to make a metaphor between this situation and contrasting the study of non-conservative flows with the study of conservative flows. Seems reasonable enough to me!
I don’t believe I claimed that he did. When I expressed not understanding the relevance or even meaning of his notation, all I got in reply was more poetic waxing. By contrast, your clear and to the point explanation made sense to this lowly ex-physicist. So, I am not sure which part of my reply was uncharitable… Anyway, JS is now on my rather short list of people not worth engaging with in an online discussion.
So, I am not sure which part of my reply was uncharitable...
The part where you accuse him of a “status smash” after he directly answered what J was (that is, the composition of those two maps) and why it was important (that is, because it reflects the symplectic structure). The only lack of productivity is this thread is yours.
Anyway, JS is now on my rather short list of people not worth engaging with in an online discussion.
These sorts of declarations always remind me of Sophist:
STRANGER: The attempt at universal separation is the final annihilation of all reasoning; for only by the union of conceptions with one another do we attain to discourse of reason.
Thurston’s gentle, thoughtful, and scrupulously polite response On proof and progress in mathematics (Bull. AMS 1994, arXiv:math/9307227, 389 citations) has emerged as a classic of the mathematical literature, and is recommended to modern students by many mathematical luminaries (Terry Tao’s weblog sidebar has a permanent link to it, for example).
Conclusion It is no bad thing for students to be familiar with this literature, which plainly shows us that it is neither necessary, nor feasible, nor desirable for everyone to think alike!
Shminux, it may be that you will find that your concerns are substantially addressed by Joshua Landsberg’s Clash of Cultures essay (2012), which is cited above.
“These conversations [are] very stressful to all involved … there are language and even philosophical barriers to be overcome.”
Thank you for your gracious remarks, Paper-Machine. Please let me add, that few (or possibly none) of the math/physics themes of the preceding posts are original to me (that’s why I give so many references!)
Students of quantum history will find pulled-back/non-linear metric and symplectic quantum dynamical flows discussed as far back as Paul Dirac’s seminal Note on exchange phenomena in the Thomas atom (1930); a free-as-in-freedom review of the nonlinear quantum dynamical frameworks that came from Dirac’s work (nowadays called the “Dirac-Frenkel-McLachlan variational principle”) is Christian Lubich’s recent On Variational Approximations In Quantum Molecular Dynamics (Math. Comp., 2004).
There is a considerable overlap between Scott Aaronson’s “freebit” hypothesis and the view of quantum mechanics that Walter Kohn’s expresses in his Electronic Structure of Matter lecture (views whose origin Kohn ascribes to Van Vleck):
Kohn’s Provocative Statement In general the many-electron wavefunction
) for a system of N electrons is not a legitimate scientific concept, when NgeN_0, where N_0approx103.
Scott’s essay would (as it seems to me) be stronger if it referenced the views of Kohn (and Van Vleck too) … especially given Walter Kohn’s unique status as the most-cited quantum scientist in all of history!
Walter Kohn’s vivid account of how his “magically” powerful quantum simulation formalism grew from strictly “muggle” roots—namely, the study of disordered intermetallic alloys—is plenty of fun too, and eerily foreshadows some of the hilarious scientific themes of Eliezer Yudkowsky’s Harry Potter and the Methods of Rationality.
In view of these nonpareil theoretical, experimental, mathematical (and nowadays) engineering successes, sustained over many decades, it is implausible (as it seems to me) that the final word has been said in praise of nonlinear quantum dynamical flows! Happy reading Shminux (and everyone else too)!
Quantum aficionados in the mold of Eliezer Yudkowsky will have fun looking up “Noether’s Theorem” in the index to Michael Spivak’s well-regardedPhysics for Mathematicians: Mechanics I, because near to it we notice an irresistible index entry “Muggles, 576″, which turns out to be a link to:
Theorem The flow of any Hamiltonian vector field consists of canonical transformations
Proof (Hogwarts version) …
Proof (Muggles version) …
Remark It is striking that Dirac’s The Principles of Quantum Mechanics (1930), Feynman’s Lectures on Physics (1965), Nielsen and Chuang’s Quantum Computation and Quantum Information (2000)---and Scott Aaronson’s essay The Ghost in the Turing Machine (2013) too—all frame their analysis exclusively in terms of (what Michael Spivak aptly calls) Muggle mathematic methods! :)
Observation Joshua Landsberg has written an essay Clash of Cultures (2012) that discusses the sustained tension between Michael Spivak’s “Hogwarts math versus Muggle math”. The tension has historical roots that extent at least as far back as Karl Gauss’ celebrated apprehension regarding the “the clamor of the Boeotians” (aka Muggles).
Conclusion Michael Spivak’s wry mathematical jokes and Eliezer Yudkowsky’s wonderfully funny Harry Potter and the Methods of Rationality both help us to appreciate that outdated Muggle-mathematical idioms of standard textbooks and philosophical analysis are a substantial impediment to 21st Century learning and rational discourse of all varieties—including philosophical discourse.
The thing you link to is not anything by Joshua Landsberg, but another of your own comments.
That in turn does link to something by Landsberg that has a section headed “Clash of cultures” but it could not by any reasonable stretch be called an essay. It’s only a few paragraphs long and about half of it is a quotation from Plato. (It also makes no explicit allusion to Spivak’s Hogwarts-Muggles distinction, though I agree it’s pointing at much the same divergence.)
gjm avers “Landsberg that has a section headed “Clash of cultures” but it could not by any reasonable stretch be called an essay. It’s only a few paragraphs long.”
LOL … gjm, you must really dislike Lincoln’s ultra-short Gettysburg Address!
More seriously, isn’t the key question whether Landsberg’s essay is correct to assert that “there are language and even philosophical barriers to be overcome”, in communicating modern geometric insights to STEM researchers trained in older mathematical techniques?
Most seriously of all, gjm, please let me express the hope that the various references that you have pursued have helped to awaken an appreciation of the severe and regrettable mathematical limitations that are inherent in the essays of Less Wrong’sQuantum Physics Sequence, including in particular Eliezer_Yudkowsky’s essay Quantum Physics Revealed As Non-Mysterious.
The burgeoning 21st century literature of geometric dynamics helps us to appreciate that the the 20th century mathematical toolkit of Less Wrong’s quantum essays perhaps will turn out to be not so much “less wrong” as “not even wrong,” in the sense that Less Wrong’s quantum essays are devoid of the geometric dynamical ideas that are flowering so vigorously in the contemporary STEM literature.
This is of course very good news for young researchers! :)
you must really dislike Lincoln’s ultra-short Gettysburg Address!
No, I think it’s excellent (though I prefer the PowerPoint version), but it isn’t an essay.
let me express the hope that the various references [...] have helped to awaken an appreciation of the [...] mathematical limitations that are inherent in [...] Less Wrong’s Quantum Physics Sequence
That sentence appears to me to embody some assumptions you’re not in a position to make reliably. Notably: That I think, or thought until John Sidles kindly enlightened me, that Eliezer’s QM essays are anything like a complete exposition of QM. As it happens, that wasn’t my opinion; for that matter I doubt it is or was even Eliezer’s.
In particular, when Eliezer says that QM is “non-mysterious” I don’t think he means that everything about it is understood, that there are no further scientific puzzles to solve. He certainly doesn’t mean it isn’t possible to pick a mathematical framework for talking about QM and then contemplate generalizations. He’s arguing against a particular sort of mysterianism one often hears in connection with QM—the sort that says, roughly, “QM is counterintuitive, which means no one really understands it or can be expected to understand it, so the right attitude towards QM is one of quasi-mystical awe”, which is the kind of thing that makes Chopraesque quantum woo get treated with less contempt than it deserves.
Even Newtonian mechanics is mysterious in the sense that there are unsolved problems associated with it. (For instance: What are all the periodic 3-body trajectories? What is the right way to think about the weird measure-zero situations—involving collisions of more than two particles—in which the usual rules of Newtonian dynamics constrain what happens next without, prima facie, fully determining it?) But no one talks about Newtonian mechanics in the silly way some people talk about quantum mechanics, and it’s that sort of quantum silliness Eliezer is (at least, as I understand it) arguing against.
I think at least one of us has a serious misunderstanding of what’s generally meant by the phrase “not even wrong”. To me, it means “sufficiently vague or confused that it doesn’t even yield the sort of testable predictions that would allow it to be refuted”, which doesn’t seem to me to be an accurate description of conventional 20th-century quantum mechanics. It might, indeed, turn out that conventional 20th-century QM is a severely incomplete description of reality, and that in some situations it gives badly wrong predictions, and that some such generalization as you favour will do better, much as relativity and QM improved on classical physics in ways that radically revised our picture of what the universe fundamentally is. But classical physics was not “not even wrong”. It was an excellent body of ideas. It explained a lot, and it enabled a lot of correct predictions and useful inventions. It was wrong but clear and useful. It was the exact opposite of “not even wrong”.
Finally and incidentally: What impression do you think your tone gives to your readers? What impression are you hoping for? I ask because I think the reality may not match your hopes.
gjm avers: ‘When Eliezer says that QM is “non-mysterious’ … He’s arguing against a particular sort of mysterianism”
That may or may not be the case, but there is zero doubt that this assertion provides rhetorical foundations for the essay And the Winner is… Many-Worlds!.
A valuable service of the mathematical literature relating to geometric mechanics is that it instills a prudent humility regarding assertions like “the Winner is… Many-Worlds!” A celebrated meditation of Alexander Grothendieck expresses this humility:
“A different image came to me a few weeks ago. The unknown thing to be known appeared to me as some stretch of earth or hard marl, resisting penetration … the sea advances insensibly in silence, nothing seems to happen, nothing moves, the water is so far off you hardly hear it … yet it finally surrounds the resistant substance.”
Surely in regard quantum mechanics, the water of our understanding is far from covering the rocks of our ignorance!
As for the tone of my posts, the intent is that people who enjoy references and quotations will take no offense, and people who do not enjoy them can simply pass by.
It seems perfectly possible to me—I make no claims about whether it’s actually true—that the following could all be the case. (1) Of the various physical theories in the possession of the human race that are definite enough to be assessed, one of the clear winners is the Standard Model. (2) Of the various ways to understand the quantum mechanics involved in the Standard Model, the clear winner is “many worlds”. (3) The known lacunae in our understanding of physics make it clear that further conceptual advances will be needed before we can claim to understand everything. (4) Those conceptual advances could take just about any form, and everything we currently think we know is potentially up for grabs. (5) “Many worlds” is not uniquely under threat from these future conceptual advances—everything is up for grabs—and the possibility of future conceptual revolutions doesn’t call for any more caution about “many worlds” than it does for caution about, say, the inseparability of space and time.
In other words: The fact that science is hard and not yet finished is indeed reason for epistemic humility—about everything; but pointing to some particular thing alleged to be a discovery of modern science and saying “no, wait, it could turn out to be wrong” is not justifiable by that fact alone, unless you are happy to do the same for all other alleged discoveries of modern science.
My guess is that you have some other reasons for being skeptical about the many-worlds interpretation, besides the very general fact that quantum mechanics might some day be the subject of a great scientific upheaval. But you haven’t said what they are.
My point about your tone is not concerned with the fact that you include references and quotations, and taking offence isn’t the failure mode you might need to worry about. The danger, rather, is that you come across as pushing, with an air of smug superiority, a non-standard view of the present state of science, and that this is liable to pattern-match in people’s brains to a host of outright cranks. If you prefer not to be dismissed as a crank, you might want to adjust your tone.
(If, on the other hand, you don’t care whether you are dismissed as a crank, then the question in some minds will be “Why should I take him seriously when he doesn’t seem to do so himself?”.)
gjm asserts “Of the various ways to understand the quantum mechanics involved in the Standard Model, the clear winner is “many worlds”
LOL … by that lenient standard, the first racehorse out of the gate, or the first sprinter out of the blocks, can reasonably be proclaimed “the clear winner” … before the race is even finished!
That’s a rational announcement only for very short races. Surely there is very little evidence that the course that finishes at comprehensive understanding of Nature’s dynamics … is a short course?
I believe you’re being uncharitable. JS is a bit effervescent and waxes poetic in a few places, but doesn’t say anything obviously wrong.
I would have assumed (perhaps wrongly) that you’d know how to take the Lie derivative of a (1, 1)-tensor field, and there’s only a short Googling necessary to ascertain that complex structures are certain kinds of (1, 1)-tensor fields. The linked draft is pretty clear about what L_X(J) = 0 means, and that makes it clear what L_X(J) != 0 means—X doesn’t generate holomorphic flows.
In another comment, he shows how to construct a compatible (almost) complex structure J from a Riemannian structure g and a symplectic structure w. This is actually a special case of a theorem of Arnol’d, which states that fixing any two yields a compatible choice of the third. (I’ve always heard this called the “two out of three” theorem, but apparently some computer science thing has overtaken this name.) This shows that J is actually relevant to the dynamics of the underlying system—just as relevant as the symplectic structure is.
From that, it’s not too much of a stretch to make a metaphor between this situation and contrasting the study of non-conservative flows with the study of conservative flows. Seems reasonable enough to me!
I don’t believe I claimed that he did. When I expressed not understanding the relevance or even meaning of his notation, all I got in reply was more poetic waxing. By contrast, your clear and to the point explanation made sense to this lowly ex-physicist. So, I am not sure which part of my reply was uncharitable… Anyway, JS is now on my rather short list of people not worth engaging with in an online discussion.
The part where you accuse him of a “status smash” after he directly answered what J was (that is, the composition of those two maps) and why it was important (that is, because it reflects the symplectic structure). The only lack of productivity is this thread is yours.
These sorts of declarations always remind me of Sophist:
Huh, I guess I am not alone in being Sidles-averse, for the same reasons.
Shminux, perhaps some Less Wrong readers will enjoy the larger reflection of our differing perspectives that is provided by Arthur Jaffe and Frank Quinn’s ‘Theoretical mathematics’: Toward a cultural synthesis of mathematics and theoretical physics (Bull. AMS 1993, arXiv:math/9307227, 188 citations); an article that was notable for its biting criticism of Bill Thurston’s geometrization program.
Thurston’s gentle, thoughtful, and scrupulously polite response On proof and progress in mathematics (Bull. AMS 1994, arXiv:math/9307227, 389 citations) has emerged as a classic of the mathematical literature, and is recommended to modern students by many mathematical luminaries (Terry Tao’s weblog sidebar has a permanent link to it, for example).
Conclusion It is no bad thing for students to be familiar with this literature, which plainly shows us that it is neither necessary, nor feasible, nor desirable for everyone to think alike!
That’s a little out of context...I think the stranger literally means the union of concepts, not the union of opinions or points of view.
I see. Well, I very much appreciate your feedback, it’s good to know how what I say comes across. I will ponder it further.
Shminux, it may be that you will find that your concerns are substantially addressed by Joshua Landsberg’s Clash of Cultures essay (2012), which is cited above.
Thank you for your gracious remarks, Paper-Machine. Please let me add, that few (or possibly none) of the math/physics themes of the preceding posts are original to me (that’s why I give so many references!)
Students of quantum history will find pulled-back/non-linear metric and symplectic quantum dynamical flows discussed as far back as Paul Dirac’s seminal Note on exchange phenomena in the Thomas atom (1930); a free-as-in-freedom review of the nonlinear quantum dynamical frameworks that came from Dirac’s work (nowadays called the “Dirac-Frenkel-McLachlan variational principle”) is Christian Lubich’s recent On Variational Approximations In Quantum Molecular Dynamics (Math. Comp., 2004).
Shminux, perhaps your appetite for nonlinear quantum dynamical theories would be whetted by reading the most-cited article in the history of physics, which is Walter Kohn and Lu Jeu Sham’s Self-Consistent Equations Including Exchange and Correlation Effects (1965, cited by 29670); a lively followup article is Walter Kohn’s Electronic Structure of Matter, which can be read as a good-humored celebration of the practical merits of varietal pullbacks … or as Walter Kohn calls them, variational Ansatzes, having a varietal product form.
There is a considerable overlap between Scott Aaronson’s “freebit” hypothesis and the view of quantum mechanics that Walter Kohn’s expresses in his Electronic Structure of Matter lecture (views whose origin Kohn ascribes to Van Vleck):
Scott’s essay would (as it seems to me) be stronger if it referenced the views of Kohn (and Van Vleck too) … especially given Walter Kohn’s unique status as the most-cited quantum scientist in all of history!
Walter Kohn’s vivid account of how his “magically” powerful quantum simulation formalism grew from strictly “muggle” roots—namely, the study of disordered intermetallic alloys—is plenty of fun too, and eerily foreshadows some of the hilarious scientific themes of Eliezer Yudkowsky’s Harry Potter and the Methods of Rationality.
In view of these nonpareil theoretical, experimental, mathematical (and nowadays) engineering successes, sustained over many decades, it is implausible (as it seems to me) that the final word has been said in praise of nonlinear quantum dynamical flows! Happy reading Shminux (and everyone else too)!
Quantum aficionados in the mold of Eliezer Yudkowsky will have fun looking up “Noether’s Theorem” in the index to Michael Spivak’s well-regarded Physics for Mathematicians: Mechanics I, because near to it we notice an irresistible index entry “Muggles, 576″, which turns out to be a link to:
Remark It is striking that Dirac’s The Principles of Quantum Mechanics (1930), Feynman’s Lectures on Physics (1965), Nielsen and Chuang’s Quantum Computation and Quantum Information (2000)---and Scott Aaronson’s essay The Ghost in the Turing Machine (2013) too—all frame their analysis exclusively in terms of (what Michael Spivak aptly calls) Muggle mathematic methods! :)
Observation Joshua Landsberg has written an essay Clash of Cultures (2012) that discusses the sustained tension between Michael Spivak’s “Hogwarts math versus Muggle math”. The tension has historical roots that extent at least as far back as Karl Gauss’ celebrated apprehension regarding the “the clamor of the Boeotians” (aka Muggles).
Conclusion Michael Spivak’s wry mathematical jokes and Eliezer Yudkowsky’s wonderfully funny Harry Potter and the Methods of Rationality both help us to appreciate that outdated Muggle-mathematical idioms of standard textbooks and philosophical analysis are a substantial impediment to 21st Century learning and rational discourse of all varieties—including philosophical discourse.
The thing you link to is not anything by Joshua Landsberg, but another of your own comments.
That in turn does link to something by Landsberg that has a section headed “Clash of cultures” but it could not by any reasonable stretch be called an essay. It’s only a few paragraphs long and about half of it is a quotation from Plato. (It also makes no explicit allusion to Spivak’s Hogwarts-Muggles distinction, though I agree it’s pointing at much the same divergence.)
LOL … gjm, you must really dislike Lincoln’s ultra-short Gettysburg Address!
More seriously, isn’t the key question whether Landsberg’s essay is correct to assert that “there are language and even philosophical barriers to be overcome”, in communicating modern geometric insights to STEM researchers trained in older mathematical techniques?
Most seriously of all, gjm, please let me express the hope that the various references that you have pursued have helped to awaken an appreciation of the severe and regrettable mathematical limitations that are inherent in the essays of Less Wrong’s Quantum Physics Sequence, including in particular Eliezer_Yudkowsky’s essay Quantum Physics Revealed As Non-Mysterious.
The burgeoning 21st century literature of geometric dynamics helps us to appreciate that the the 20th century mathematical toolkit of Less Wrong’s quantum essays perhaps will turn out to be not so much “less wrong” as “not even wrong,” in the sense that Less Wrong’s quantum essays are devoid of the geometric dynamical ideas that are flowering so vigorously in the contemporary STEM literature.
This is of course very good news for young researchers! :)
No, I think it’s excellent (though I prefer the PowerPoint version), but it isn’t an essay.
That sentence appears to me to embody some assumptions you’re not in a position to make reliably. Notably: That I think, or thought until John Sidles kindly enlightened me, that Eliezer’s QM essays are anything like a complete exposition of QM. As it happens, that wasn’t my opinion; for that matter I doubt it is or was even Eliezer’s.
In particular, when Eliezer says that QM is “non-mysterious” I don’t think he means that everything about it is understood, that there are no further scientific puzzles to solve. He certainly doesn’t mean it isn’t possible to pick a mathematical framework for talking about QM and then contemplate generalizations. He’s arguing against a particular sort of mysterianism one often hears in connection with QM—the sort that says, roughly, “QM is counterintuitive, which means no one really understands it or can be expected to understand it, so the right attitude towards QM is one of quasi-mystical awe”, which is the kind of thing that makes Chopraesque quantum woo get treated with less contempt than it deserves.
Even Newtonian mechanics is mysterious in the sense that there are unsolved problems associated with it. (For instance: What are all the periodic 3-body trajectories? What is the right way to think about the weird measure-zero situations—involving collisions of more than two particles—in which the usual rules of Newtonian dynamics constrain what happens next without, prima facie, fully determining it?) But no one talks about Newtonian mechanics in the silly way some people talk about quantum mechanics, and it’s that sort of quantum silliness Eliezer is (at least, as I understand it) arguing against.
I think at least one of us has a serious misunderstanding of what’s generally meant by the phrase “not even wrong”. To me, it means “sufficiently vague or confused that it doesn’t even yield the sort of testable predictions that would allow it to be refuted”, which doesn’t seem to me to be an accurate description of conventional 20th-century quantum mechanics. It might, indeed, turn out that conventional 20th-century QM is a severely incomplete description of reality, and that in some situations it gives badly wrong predictions, and that some such generalization as you favour will do better, much as relativity and QM improved on classical physics in ways that radically revised our picture of what the universe fundamentally is. But classical physics was not “not even wrong”. It was an excellent body of ideas. It explained a lot, and it enabled a lot of correct predictions and useful inventions. It was wrong but clear and useful. It was the exact opposite of “not even wrong”.
Finally and incidentally: What impression do you think your tone gives to your readers? What impression are you hoping for? I ask because I think the reality may not match your hopes.
That may or may not be the case, but there is zero doubt that this assertion provides rhetorical foundations for the essay And the Winner is… Many-Worlds!.
A valuable service of the mathematical literature relating to geometric mechanics is that it instills a prudent humility regarding assertions like “the Winner is… Many-Worlds!” A celebrated meditation of Alexander Grothendieck expresses this humility:
Surely in regard quantum mechanics, the water of our understanding is far from covering the rocks of our ignorance!
As for the tone of my posts, the intent is that people who enjoy references and quotations will take no offense, and people who do not enjoy them can simply pass by.
It seems perfectly possible to me—I make no claims about whether it’s actually true—that the following could all be the case. (1) Of the various physical theories in the possession of the human race that are definite enough to be assessed, one of the clear winners is the Standard Model. (2) Of the various ways to understand the quantum mechanics involved in the Standard Model, the clear winner is “many worlds”. (3) The known lacunae in our understanding of physics make it clear that further conceptual advances will be needed before we can claim to understand everything. (4) Those conceptual advances could take just about any form, and everything we currently think we know is potentially up for grabs. (5) “Many worlds” is not uniquely under threat from these future conceptual advances—everything is up for grabs—and the possibility of future conceptual revolutions doesn’t call for any more caution about “many worlds” than it does for caution about, say, the inseparability of space and time.
In other words: The fact that science is hard and not yet finished is indeed reason for epistemic humility—about everything; but pointing to some particular thing alleged to be a discovery of modern science and saying “no, wait, it could turn out to be wrong” is not justifiable by that fact alone, unless you are happy to do the same for all other alleged discoveries of modern science.
My guess is that you have some other reasons for being skeptical about the many-worlds interpretation, besides the very general fact that quantum mechanics might some day be the subject of a great scientific upheaval. But you haven’t said what they are.
My point about your tone is not concerned with the fact that you include references and quotations, and taking offence isn’t the failure mode you might need to worry about. The danger, rather, is that you come across as pushing, with an air of smug superiority, a non-standard view of the present state of science, and that this is liable to pattern-match in people’s brains to a host of outright cranks. If you prefer not to be dismissed as a crank, you might want to adjust your tone.
(If, on the other hand, you don’t care whether you are dismissed as a crank, then the question in some minds will be “Why should I take him seriously when he doesn’t seem to do so himself?”.)
LOL … by that lenient standard, the first racehorse out of the gate, or the first sprinter out of the blocks, can reasonably be proclaimed “the clear winner” … before the race is even finished!
That’s a rational announcement only for very short races. Surely there is very little evidence that the course that finishes at comprehensive understanding of Nature’s dynamics … is a short course?
As for my own opinions in regard to quantum dynamical systems, they are more along the lines of here are some questions that are mathematically well-posed and are interesting to engineers and scientists alike … and definitely not along the lines of “here are the answers to those questions”!
Actually I clearly and explicitly went out of my way to say I wasn’t asserting that.
Bored of being laughed at out loud now. (Twice in one short thread is enough.) Bye.
Goodbye, gjm. The impetus that your posts provided to post thought-provoking mathematical links will be missed. :)