Plato’s notion of “perfection”, which included his belief that there is exactly one “perfect” society, and that our goal should be to do ABSOLUTELY ANYTHING NO MATTER HOW HORRIBLE to construct it, and then do ABSOLUTELY ANYTHING NO MATTER HOW HORRIBLE to make sure it STAYS THAT WAY FOREVER.
Citation needed. I’ve read The Republic , and there’s nothing remotely like that in it.
Republic is the reference. I’m not going to take the hours it would take to give book-and-paragraph citations, because either you haven’t read the the entire Republic, or else you’ve read it, but you want to argue that each of the many terrible things he wrote don’t actually represent Plato’s opinion or desire.
(You know it’s a big book, right? 89,000 words in the Greek. If you read it in a collection or anthology, it wasn’t the whole Republic.)
The task of arguing over what in /Republic/ Plato approves or disapproves of is arduous and, I think, unnecessary.
First, everybody agrees that the topic of Republic is “social justice”, and Plato makes his position on that clear, in Republic and in his other works: Justice is when everybody accepts the job and the class they’re born into, without any grumbling or backtalk, and Plato is king and tells everybody what to do. His conclusion, that justice is when everybody minds their own business (meaning they don’t get involved in politics, which should be the business of philosophers), is clearly meant as a direct refutation of Pericles’ summary of Athenian values in his famous funeral oration: “We do not say that a man who shows no interest in politics is a man who minds his own business; we say that he has no business here at all.”
When the topic of the book is social justice, and you get to the end and it says “Justice is when everyone does what I say and stays in their place”, you should throw that book in the trash.
(This is a bit unfair to Plato, because the Greek word he used meant something more like “righteousness”. “justice” is a lousy translation. But this doesn’t matter to me, because I don’t care what Plato meant as much as I care about how people use it; and the Western tradition is to say that Plato was talking about justice. And it’s still a totalitarian conclusion, whether you call it “justice” or “righteousness”.)
This view of justice (or righteousness) is consistent with his life and his writings. He seems to support slavery as natural and proper, though he never talks about it directly; see Vlastos 1941, Slavery in Plato’s Thought. He literally /invented/ racism, in order to theorize that a stable, race-based state, in which the inferior races were completely conditioned and situated so as to be incapable of either having or acting on independent desires or thoughts, would have neither the unrest due to social mobility that democratic Athens had, nor the periodic slave revolts that Sparta had. He and his clan preferred Sparta to Athens; his uncle, a fellow student of Socrates, was the tyrant of Athens in 404 BC, appointed by Sparta; and murdered 1500 Athenian citizens, mostly for supporting democracy. Socrates was probably executed in 399 BC not for being a “gadfly”, but because the Athenians believed that they’d lost the war with Sparta thanks to the collusion of Socrates’ students with Sparta.
Plato had personal, up-close experience of the construction of a bloody totalitarian state, and far from ever expressing a word of disapproval of it, he mocked at least one of its victims in Republic, and continued to advocate totalitarian policies in his writings, such as /The Laws/. He was a wealthy aristocrat who wanted to destroy democracy and bring back the good old days when you couldn’t be taken to court just for killing a slave, as evidenced by the scorn he heaps on working people and merchants in many of his dialogues, and also his jabs at Athens and democracy; and by the Euthyphro, a dialogue with a man who’s a fool for taking his father to court for killing a slave.
One common defense of Plato is that his preferred State was the first state he described, the “true state”, in which everyone gets just what they need to survive; he actually detested the second, “fevered state”, in which people have luxuries (which, he says, can only ever be had by theft and war—property is theft!)
I find this implausible, or at best hypocritical, for several reasons.
It’s in line with the persona of Socrates, but not at all in line with Plato’s actual life of luxury as a powerful and wealthy man.
Plato spends a few paragraphs describing the “true state”, and the rest of Republic describing the “fevered state” or defending or elaborating on its controversial aspects.
He supports the totalitarian polices, such as banning all music, poetry, and art other than government propaganda, with arguments which are sometimes solid if you accept Plato’s philosophy.
Many of the controversial aspects of the “fevered state” are copied from Sparta, which Plato admired, and which his friends and family fought for against their own city; and direct opposites of Athens, which he hated.
The simplest reading of Republic, I think, is that the second state he described is one he liked to dream about, but knew wasn’t plausible.
But my second reason for thinking this debate over Plato’s intent is unimportant is that people don’t usually read Republic for its brief description of the “true state”. Either they just read the first 2 or 3 books and a few other extracts carefully chosen by professors to avoid all the nasty stuff and give the impression that Plato was legitimately trying to figure out what justice means like he claimed; or they read it to get off on the radical policies of the fevered state (which is the political equivalent of BDSM porn).
Some of the policies of that state include: breeding citizens like cattle into races that must be kept distinct, with philosophers telling everyone whom to have sex with, sometimes requiring brothers and sisters to have sex with each other (5.461e); allowing soldiers on campaign to rape any citizen they want to (5.468c); dictating jobs by race; abolishing all art, poetry, and music except government propaganda; banning independent philosophy; the death sentence for repeatedly questioning authority; forbidding doctors from wasting their time on people who are no longer useful to the State because they’re old or permanently injured; forced abortions of all children conceived without the State’s permission (including for all women over age 40 and all men over age 55); forbidding romantic love, marriage, or raising your own children; outlawing private property (5.464); allowing any citizen to violently assault any other citizen, in order to encourage citizens to stay physically fit (5.464e); and founding of the city by killing everyone over the age, IIRC, of 10. (He writes “exiling”, but you would have to kill them to get them all to give up their children; see e.g. Cambodia).
The closest anybody ever came to implementing the ideas in /Republic/ (which was not a republic, and which Plato actually titled /Polis/, “The State”) was Sparta (which it was obviously based on). The second-closest was Nazi Germany (also patterned partly on Sparta). /Brave New World/ is also similar, though much freer.
Citation needed. I’ve read The Republic , and there’s nothing remotely like that in it.
Republic is the reference. I’m not going to take the hours it would take to give book-and-paragraph citations, because either you haven’t read the the entire Republic, or else you’ve read it, but you want to argue that each of the many terrible things he wrote don’t actually represent Plato’s opinion or desire.
(You know it’s a big book, right? 89,000 words in the Greek. If you read it in a collection or anthology, it wasn’t the whole Republic.)
The task of arguing over what in /Republic/ Plato approves or disapproves of is arduous and, I think, unnecessary.
First, everybody agrees that the topic of Republic is “social justice”, and Plato makes his position on that clear, in Republic and in his other works: Justice is when everybody accepts the job and the class they’re born into, without any grumbling or backtalk, and Plato is king and tells everybody what to do. His conclusion, that justice is when everybody minds their own business (meaning they don’t get involved in politics, which should be the business of philosophers), is clearly meant as a direct refutation of Pericles’ summary of Athenian values in his famous funeral oration: “We do not say that a man who shows no interest in politics is a man who minds his own business; we say that he has no business here at all.”
When the topic of the book is social justice, and you get to the end and it says “Justice is when everyone does what I say and stays in their place”, you should throw that book in the trash.
(This is a bit unfair to Plato, because the Greek word he used meant something more like “righteousness”. “justice” is a lousy translation. But this doesn’t matter to me, because I don’t care what Plato meant as much as I care about how people use it; and the Western tradition is to say that Plato was talking about justice. And it’s still a totalitarian conclusion, whether you call it “justice” or “righteousness”.)
This view of justice (or righteousness) is consistent with his life and his writings. He seems to support slavery as natural and proper, though he never talks about it directly; see Vlastos 1941, Slavery in Plato’s Thought. He literally /invented/ racism, in order to theorize that a stable, race-based state, in which the inferior races were completely conditioned and situated so as to be incapable of either having or acting on independent desires or thoughts, would have neither the unrest due to social mobility that democratic Athens had, nor the periodic slave revolts that Sparta had. He and his clan preferred Sparta to Athens; his uncle, a fellow student of Socrates, was the tyrant of Athens in 404 BC, appointed by Sparta; and murdered 1500 Athenian citizens, mostly for supporting democracy. Socrates was probably executed in 399 BC not for being a “gadfly”, but because the Athenians believed that they’d lost the war with Sparta thanks to the collusion of Socrates’ students with Sparta.
Plato had personal, up-close experience of the construction of a bloody totalitarian state, and far from ever expressing a word of disapproval of it, he mocked at least one of its victims in Republic, and continued to advocate totalitarian policies in his writings, such as /The Laws/. He was a wealthy aristocrat who wanted to destroy democracy and bring back the good old days when you couldn’t be taken to court just for killing a slave, as evidenced by the scorn he heaps on working people and merchants in many of his dialogues, and also his jabs at Athens and democracy; and by the Euthyphro, a dialogue with a man who’s a fool for taking his father to court for killing a slave.
One common defense of Plato is that his preferred State was the first state he described, the “true state”, in which everyone gets just what they need to survive; he actually detested the second, “fevered state”, in which people have luxuries (which, he says, can only ever be had by theft and war—property is theft!)
I find this implausible, or at best hypocritical, for several reasons.
It’s in line with the persona of Socrates, but not at all in line with Plato’s actual life of luxury as a powerful and wealthy man.
Plato spends a few paragraphs describing the “true state”, and the rest of Republic describing the “fevered state” or defending or elaborating on its controversial aspects.
He supports the totalitarian polices, such as banning all music, poetry, and art other than government propaganda, with arguments which are sometimes solid if you accept Plato’s philosophy.
Many of the controversial aspects of the “fevered state” are copied from Sparta, which Plato admired, and which his friends and family fought for against their own city; and direct opposites of Athens, which he hated.
The simplest reading of Republic, I think, is that the second state he described is one he liked to dream about, but knew wasn’t plausible.
But my second reason for thinking this debate over Plato’s intent is unimportant is that people don’t usually read Republic for its brief description of the “true state”. Either they just read the first 2 or 3 books and a few other extracts carefully chosen by professors to avoid all the nasty stuff and give the impression that Plato was legitimately trying to figure out what justice means like he claimed; or they read it to get off on the radical policies of the fevered state (which is the political equivalent of BDSM porn).
Some of the policies of that state include: breeding citizens like cattle into races that must be kept distinct, with philosophers telling everyone whom to have sex with, sometimes requiring brothers and sisters to have sex with each other (5.461e); allowing soldiers on campaign to rape any citizen they want to (5.468c); dictating jobs by race; abolishing all art, poetry, and music except government propaganda; banning independent philosophy; the death sentence for repeatedly questioning authority; forbidding doctors from wasting their time on people who are no longer useful to the State because they’re old or permanently injured; forced abortions of all children conceived without the State’s permission (including for all women over age 40 and all men over age 55); forbidding romantic love, marriage, or raising your own children; outlawing private property (5.464); allowing any citizen to violently assault any other citizen, in order to encourage citizens to stay physically fit (5.464e); and founding of the city by killing everyone over the age, IIRC, of 10. (He writes “exiling”, but you would have to kill them to get them all to give up their children; see e.g. Cambodia).
The closest anybody ever came to implementing the ideas in /Republic/ (which was not a republic, and which Plato actually titled /Polis/, “The State”) was Sparta (which it was obviously based on). The second-closest was Nazi Germany (also patterned partly on Sparta). /Brave New World/ is also similar, though much freer.
I read the Bloom translation all the way through. Maybe you could tell me which translation you read all the way through.
Yes. Have you?
Then I’m not going to believe you.
See the 2nd-to-last paragraph of my revised comment above, and see if any of it jogs your memory.