Similarity Clusters
Once upon a time, the philosophers of Plato’s Academy claimed that the best definition of human was a “featherless biped”. Diogenes of Sinope, also called Diogenes the Cynic, is said to have promptly exhibited a plucked chicken and declared “Here is Plato’s man.” The Platonists promptly changed their definition to “a featherless biped with broad nails”.
No dictionary, no encyclopedia, has ever listed all the things that humans have in common. We have red blood, five fingers on each of two hands, bony skulls, 23 pairs of chromosomes—but the same might be said of other animal species. We make complex tools to make complex tools, we use syntactical combinatorial language, we harness critical fission reactions as a source of energy: these things may serve out to single out only humans, but not all humans—many of us have never built a fission reactor. With the right set of necessary-and-sufficient gene sequences you could single out all humans, and only humans—at least for now—but it would still be far from all that humans have in common.
But so long as you don’t happen to be near a plucked chicken, saying “Look for featherless bipeds” may serve to pick out a few dozen of the particular things that are humans, as opposed to houses, vases, sandwiches, cats, colors, or mathematical theorems.
Once the definition “featherless biped” has been bound to some particular featherless bipeds, you can look over the group, and begin harvesting some of the other characteristics—beyond mere featherfree twolegginess—that the “featherless bipeds” seem to share in common. The particular featherless bipeds that you see seem to also use language, build complex tools, speak combinatorial language with syntax, bleed red blood if poked, die when they drink hemlock.
Thus the category “human” grows richer, and adds more and more characteristics; and when Diogenes finally presents his plucked chicken, we are not fooled: This plucked chicken is obviously not similar to the other “featherless bipeds”.
(If Aristotelian logic were a good model of human psychology, the Platonists would have looked at the plucked chicken and said, “Yes, that’s a human; what’s your point?”)
If the first featherless biped you see is a plucked chicken, then you may end up thinking that the verbal label “human” denotes a plucked chicken; so I can modify my treasure map to point to “featherless bipeds with broad nails”, and if I am wise, go on to say, “See Diogenes over there? That’s a human, and I’m a human, and you’re a human; and that chimpanzee is not a human, though fairly close.”
The initial clue only has to lead the user to the similarity cluster—the group of things that have many characteristics in common. After that, the initial clue has served its purpose, and I can go on to convey the new information “humans are currently mortal”, or whatever else I want to say about us featherless bipeds.
A dictionary is best thought of, not as a book of Aristotelian class definitions, but a book of hints for matching verbal labels to similarity clusters, or matching labels to properties that are useful in distinguishing similarity clusters.
- 37 Ways That Words Can Be Wrong by 6 Mar 2008 5:09 UTC; 229 points) (
- Where to Draw the Boundaries? by 13 Apr 2019 21:34 UTC; 124 points) (
- Meaning & Agency by 19 Dec 2023 22:27 UTC; 91 points) (
- Unnatural Categories Are Optimized for Deception by 8 Jan 2021 20:54 UTC; 89 points) (
- Arguing “By Definition” by 20 Feb 2008 23:37 UTC; 85 points) (
- Categorizing Has Consequences by 19 Feb 2008 1:40 UTC; 74 points) (
- The Argument from Common Usage by 13 Feb 2008 16:24 UTC; 62 points) (
- Reply to Nate Soares on Dolphins by 10 Jun 2021 4:53 UTC; 46 points) (
- The Design Space of Minds-In-General by 25 Jun 2008 6:37 UTC; 44 points) (
- The Nature of Logic by 15 Nov 2008 6:20 UTC; 42 points) (
- The Inadequacy of Current Science (Novum Organum Book 1: 1-37) by 23 Sep 2019 2:53 UTC; 38 points) (
- No Really, Why Aren’t Rationalists Winning? by 4 Nov 2018 18:11 UTC; 37 points) (
- 8 Apr 2013 3:36 UTC; 20 points) 's comment on Rationality Quotes April 2013 by (
- Words, Locally Defined by 3 May 2018 23:26 UTC; 19 points) (
- The “supernatural” category by 24 Mar 2011 20:52 UTC; 11 points) (
- Rationality Reading Group: Part N: A Human’s Guide to Words by 18 Nov 2015 23:50 UTC; 9 points) (
- How A Highly Sensitive Person Sees Words by 28 Jan 2022 3:16 UTC; 8 points) (
- A Hill of Validity in Defense of Meaning by 15 Jul 2023 17:57 UTC; 8 points) (
- [SEQ RERUN] Similarity Clusters by 10 Jan 2012 4:51 UTC; 7 points) (
- 30 Jul 2023 6:58 UTC; 7 points) 's comment on Yes, It’s Subjective, But Why All The Crabs? by (
- 24 Jul 2013 12:40 UTC; 7 points) 's comment on Rationality Quotes July 2013 by (
- The Map of the Map by 29 Jan 2022 10:03 UTC; 7 points) (
- 8 Aug 2012 20:24 UTC; 6 points) 's comment on Is lossless information transfer possible? by (
- 23 Mar 2012 1:24 UTC; 6 points) 's comment on Do you have High-Functioning Asperger’s Syndrome? by (
- 8 Dec 2012 21:54 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on Mixed Reference: The Great Reductionist Project by (
- 17 Aug 2023 11:41 UTC; 3 points) 's comment on Yes, It’s Subjective, But Why All The Crabs? by (
- 15 Jan 2023 21:56 UTC; 2 points) 's comment on Core Concept Conversation: What is wealth? by (
- Meetup : West LA—Inflation of Terminology by 21 Sep 2014 16:07 UTC; 2 points) (
- 22 May 2010 14:25 UTC; 1 point) 's comment on Open Thread: May 2010, Part 2 by (
- 19 Jan 2020 2:51 UTC; 1 point) 's comment on Risk and uncertainty: A false dichotomy? by (
- 31 May 2015 19:54 UTC; 0 points) 's comment on Understanding Who You Really Are by (
A nit: people with polydactyly or trisomies are still human. But that supports the larger point. See also George Lakoff’s Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things which develops a prototype model of categorization.
Sorry, newbie here. I assume that once you’ve fleshed our your similarity cluster, your initial clue may also be happily proven false, right?
I’m thinking of, say, amputees, or, ahem, furries, neither of which would match your clue, but both of which can be recognised (perhaps with some difficulty in the latter case) as humans, once you’ve gathered enough information to fill out your cluster.
Also a newbie… but I’d gather that each of the “sign-post” characteristics strongly increase the probability that the subject is a human. So, if you look for “things that are bipedal and featherless”—you have a strong likelihood of finding a human… ie it doesn’t necessarily mean that if a thing doesn’t have that characteristic, that it isn’t human ie A->Human doesn’t mean that ~A->~Human though if you find ~A then Human has lowered probability. I reckon you can probably sum across the cluster and as long as it has a good percentage of the signalling characteristics—you’d have a high chance of Human.
As to furries and plucked chickens. I’d assume that a temporary-characteristic shouldn’t be taken as a permanent characteristic. eg a plucked chicken is temporarily un-feathered (and not by its own choice either!). Normally (for that chicken) it is feathered… the opposite is the case for furries ;)
It was never specified that humans are something that stay human. Once you notice that, you’d start using “was a human” and “will be a human” as criteria. The plucked chicken clearly wasn’t a human before, and will most likely go into another obviously non-human state soon, so it doesn’t fit well as a human. The homo sapiens with the feathered suit used to be an obvious example, and soon will be again, so it fits well as a human.
It is strange to see a common machine learning algorithm explained philosophically rather than mathematically.